In mathematics, a set A is a subset of a set B if all elements of A are also elements of B; B is then a superset of A. It is possible for A and B to be equal; if they are unequal, then A is a proper subset of B. The relationship of one set being a subset of another is called inclusion (or sometimes containment). A is a subset of B may also be expressed as B includes (or contains) A or A is included (or contained) in B. A k-subset is a subset with k elements.
When quantified, A ⊆ B {\displaystyle A\subseteq B} is represented as ∀ x ( x ∈ A ⇒ x ∈ B ) . {\displaystyle \forall x\left(x\in A\Rightarrow x\in B\right).} [1]
One can prove the statement A ⊆ B {\displaystyle A\subseteq B} by applying a proof technique known as the element argument[2]:
Let sets A and B be given. To prove that A ⊆ B , {\displaystyle A\subseteq B,} suppose that a is a particular but arbitrarily chosen element of A show that a is an element of B.
Let sets A and B be given. To prove that A ⊆ B , {\displaystyle A\subseteq B,}
The validity of this technique can be seen as a consequence of universal generalization: the technique shows ( c ∈ A ) ⇒ ( c ∈ B ) {\displaystyle (c\in A)\Rightarrow (c\in B)} for an arbitrarily chosen element c. Universal generalisation then implies ∀ x ( x ∈ A ⇒ x ∈ B ) , {\displaystyle \forall x\left(x\in A\Rightarrow x\in B\right),} which is equivalent to A ⊆ B , {\displaystyle A\subseteq B,} as stated above.
If A and B are sets and every element of A is also an element of B, then:
If A is a subset of B, but A is not equal to B (i.e. there exists at least one element of B which is not an element of A), then:
The empty set, written { } {\displaystyle \{\}} or ∅ , {\displaystyle \varnothing ,} has no elements, and therefore is vacuously a subset of any set X.
Some authors use the symbols ⊂ {\displaystyle \subset } and ⊃ {\displaystyle \supset } to indicate subset and superset respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols ⊆ {\displaystyle \subseteq } and ⊇ . {\displaystyle \supseteq .} [4] For example, for these authors, it is true of every set A that A ⊂ A . {\displaystyle A\subset A.} (a reflexive relation).
Other authors prefer to use the symbols ⊂ {\displaystyle \subset } and ⊃ {\displaystyle \supset } to indicate proper (also called strict) subset and proper superset respectively; that is, with the same meaning as and instead of the symbols ⊊ {\displaystyle \subsetneq } and ⊋ . {\displaystyle \supsetneq .} [5] This usage makes ⊆ {\displaystyle \subseteq } and ⊂ {\displaystyle \subset } analogous to the inequality symbols ≤ {\displaystyle \leq } and < . {\displaystyle <.} For example, if x ≤ y , {\displaystyle x\leq y,} then x may or may not equal y, but if x < y , {\displaystyle x<y,} then x definitely does not equal y, and is less than y (an irreflexive relation). Similarly, using the convention that ⊂ {\displaystyle \subset } is proper subset, if A ⊆ B , {\displaystyle A\subseteq B,} then A may or may not equal B, but if A ⊂ B , {\displaystyle A\subset B,} then A definitely does not equal B.
Another example in an Euler diagram:
The set of all subsets of S {\displaystyle S} is called its power set, and is denoted by P ( S ) {\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(S)} .[6]
The inclusion relation ⊆ {\displaystyle \subseteq } is a partial order on the set P ( S ) {\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(S)} defined by A ≤ B ⟺ A ⊆ B {\displaystyle A\leq B\iff A\subseteq B} . We may also partially order P ( S ) {\displaystyle {\mathcal {P}}(S)} by reverse set inclusion by defining A ≤ B if and only if B ⊆ A . {\displaystyle A\leq B{\text{ if and only if }}B\subseteq A.}
For the power set P ( S ) {\displaystyle \operatorname {\mathcal {P}} (S)} of a set S, the inclusion partial order is—up to an order isomorphism—the Cartesian product of k = | S | {\displaystyle k=|S|} (the cardinality of S) copies of the partial order on { 0 , 1 } {\displaystyle \{0,1\}} for which 0 < 1. {\displaystyle 0<1.} This can be illustrated by enumerating S = { s 1 , s 2 , … , s k } , {\displaystyle S=\left\{s_{1},s_{2},\ldots ,s_{k}\right\},} , and associating with each subset T ⊆ S {\displaystyle T\subseteq S} (i.e., each element of 2 S {\displaystyle 2^{S}} ) the k-tuple from { 0 , 1 } k , {\displaystyle \{0,1\}^{k},} of which the ith coordinate is 1 if and only if s i {\displaystyle s_{i}} is a member of T.
The set of all k {\displaystyle k} -subsets of A {\displaystyle A} is denoted by ( A k ) {\displaystyle {\tbinom {A}{k}}} , in analogue with the notation for binomial coefficients, which count the number of k {\displaystyle k} -subsets of an n {\displaystyle n} -element set. In set theory, the notation [ A ] k {\displaystyle [A]^{k}} is also common, especially when k {\displaystyle k} is a transfinite cardinal number.
{{cite book}}