Share to: share facebook share twitter share wa share telegram print page

Philosophy of suicide

In ethics and other branches of philosophy, suicide poses difficult questions, answered differently by various philosophers. The French Algerian essayist, novelist, and playwright Albert Camus (1913–1960) began his philosophical essay The Myth of Sisyphus with the famous line "There is but one truly serious philosophical problem and that is suicide." (French: Il n'y a qu'un problème philosophique vraiment sérieux : c'est le suicide.).[1]

Philosophical stances on suicide can be divided into two broad groups. Religious philosophy almost universally condemns suicide, while nonreligious stances tend towards toleration, with some seeing it as laudatory, depending on circumstance. Utilitarianism offers perhaps a confusing stance. For example, using Jeremy Bentham's hedonistic calculus, it may be concluded that although suicide offers utility by ending personal suffering, the grief it causes others may outweigh its utility. The calculation cannot be determined at a philosophical level.

Arguments against suicide

Common philosophical opinion of suicide since modernization reflected a spread in cultural beliefs of western societies that suicide is immoral and unethical.[2] One popular argument is that many of the reasons for committing suicide—such as depression, emotional pain, or economic hardship—are transitory and can be ameliorated by therapy and through making changes to some aspects of one's life. A common adage in the discourse surrounding suicide prevention sums up this view: "Suicide is a permanent solution to a temporary problem." However, the argument against this is that while emotional pain may seem transitory to most people, in other cases it may be extremely difficult or even impossible to resolve, even through counseling or lifestyle change, depending upon the severity of the affliction and the person's ability to cope with their pain. Examples of this are incurable disease or lifelong mental illness.[3]

Absurdism

Camus saw the goal of absurdism in establishing whether suicide is a necessary response to a world which appears to be mute both on the question of God's existence (and thus what such an existence might answer) and for our search for meaning and purpose in the world. For Camus, suicide was the rejection of freedom. He thought that fleeing from the absurdity of reality into illusions, religion, or death is not the way out. Instead of fleeing the absurd meaninglessness of life, we should embrace life passionately.

Existentialist Sartre describes the position of Meursault, the protagonist of Camus' The Stranger who is condemned to death, in the following way:

The absurd man will not commit suicide; he wants to live, without relinquishing any of his certainty, without a future, without hope, without illusions ... and without resignation either. He stares at death with passionate attention, and this fascination liberates him. He experiences the "divine irresponsibility" of the condemned man.[4]

Christian-inspired philosophy

Christian theology almost universally condemns suicide as being a crime against God. G. K. Chesterton calls suicide "the ultimate and absolute evil, the refusal to take an interest in existence". He argues that a person who kills himself, as far as he is concerned, destroys the entire world (apparently exactly repeating Maimonides' view).

Liberalism

John Stuart Mill argued, in his influential essay "On Liberty", that since the sine qua non of liberty is the power of the individual to make choices, any choice that one might make that would deprive one of the ability to make further choices should be prevented. Thus, for Mill, selling oneself into slavery should be prevented in order to avoid precluding the ability to make further choices. Concerning these matters, Mill writes in "On Liberty":

"Not only persons are not held to engagements which violate the rights of third parties, but it is sometimes considered a sufficient reason for releasing them from an engagement, that it is injurious to themselves. In this and most other civilized countries, for example, an engagement by which a person should sell himself, or allow himself to be sold, as a slave, would be null and void; neither enforced by law nor by opinion. The ground for thus limiting his power of voluntarily disposing of his own lot in life, is apparent, and is very clearly seen in this extreme case. The reason for not interfering, unless for the sake of others, with a person's voluntary acts, is consideration for his liberty. His voluntary choice is evidence that what he so chooses is desirable, or at the least endurable, to him, and his good is on the whole best provided for by allowing him to take his own means of pursuing it. But by selling himself for a slave, he abdicates his liberty; he forgoes any future use of it, beyond that single act. He therefore defeats, in his own case, the very purpose which is the justification of allowing him to dispose of himself. He is no longer free; but is thenceforth in a position which has no longer the presumption in its favour, that would be afforded by his voluntarily remaining in it. The principle of freedom cannot require that he should be free not to be free. It is not freedom, to be allowed to alienate his freedom".[5]

It could be argued that suicide prevents further choices in the same way slavery does. However, it can also be argued that there are significant differences in not having any further involvement in decisions about your life and not having any further life to make decisions about. Suicide essentially removes the condition of being alive, not the condition of making choices about your life.

Mill believes the individual to be the best guardian of their own interests. He uses the example of a man about to cross a broken bridge: we can forcibly stop that person and warn him of the danger, but ultimately should not prevent him from crossing the bridge—for only he knows the worth of his life balanced against the danger of crossing the bridge.

Too much should not be read into "disposing of his own lot in life" in the passage, as this is not necessarily talking about anything other than slavery. Indeed, it would be odd if Mill had intended it to be about suicide but not explored the issue fully.

Deontology

From a deontological perspective, Immanuel Kant argues against suicide in Fundamental Principles of The Metaphysic of Morals. In accordance with the second formulation of his categorical imperative, Kant argues that, "He who contemplates suicide should ask himself whether his action can be consistent with the idea of humanity as an end in itself." Kant's theory looks at the act only, and not at its outcomes and consequences, and claims that one is ethically required to consider whether one would be willing to universalise the act: to claim everyone should behave that way. Kant argues that choosing to commit suicide entails considering oneself as a means to an end, which he rejects: a person, he says, must not be used "merely as means, but must in all actions always be considered as an end in himself." Furthermore, Kant argues that, since objective morality is grounded in one's own ability to reason, suicide is wrong because it involves removing that ability through ending one's life, thereby creating a kind of practical contradiction.

Social contract

The social contract, according to Jean-Jacques Rousseau, is such that every man has "a right to risk his own life in order to preserve it."

Hobbes and Locke reject the right of individuals to take their own life. Hobbes claims in his Leviathan that natural law forbids every man "to do, that which is destructive of his life, or take away the means of preserving the same." Breaking this natural law is irrational and immoral. Hobbes also states that it is intuitively rational for men to want felicity and to fear death most.

Aristotle

Aristotle in his 'discussion of courage, maintains that committing suicide to avoid pain or other undesirable circumstances is a cowardly act. In a later chapter [of Nicomachean Ethics], he further argues that suicide is unlawful and is an act committed against the interests of the state.'[6]

Plotinus

The neoplatonist philosopher Plotinus (205-270) devoted a short treatise (Ennead I, 9 = treatise 16) to the question of the legitimity of suicide (On Suicide). Discussing platonist and stocian arguments, he concludes that suicide is not allowed except when one understands that he is losing his reason. Plotinus also deals in this treatise with the temptation, for the platonist philosopher (cf Phaedo), to join the intelligible absolute, and to liberate his soul from his body through the medium of suicide.[7]

Neutral and situational stances

Honor

Japan has a form of suicide called seppuku, which is considered an honorable way to redeem oneself for transgressions or personal defeats. It was widely accepted in the days of the Samurai and even before that. It was generally seen as a privilege granted only to the samurai class; civilian criminals would thus not have this 'honor' and be executed. In this historical perspective, suicide reflects a cultural view of suicide as noble, acceptable, and even brave, rather than cowardly and wrong.

Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism can be used as a justification for or as an argument against suicide. For example, through Jeremy Bentham's hedonistic calculus, it can be concluded that although the death of a depressed person ends their suffering, the person's family and friends may grieve as well, and their pain may outweigh the release of depression of the individual through suicide.[8]

Arguments that suicide is permissible

There are arguments in favor of allowing an individual to choose between life and death by suicide. Those in favor of suicide as a personal choice reject the thought that suicide is always or usually irrational, but is instead a solution to real problems; a line of last resort that can legitimately be taken when the alternative is considered worse. They believe that no being should be made to suffer unnecessarily, and suicide provides an escape from suffering.

Idealism

Herodotus wrote: "When life is so burdensome, death has become for man a sought-after refuge". Schopenhauer affirmed: "They tell us that suicide is the greatest act of cowardice... that suicide is wrong; when it is quite obvious that there is nothing in the world to which every man has a more unassailable title than to his own life and person."[9]

Schopenhauer's main work, The World as Will and Representation, occasionally uses the act in its examples. He denied that suicide was immoral and saw it as one's right to take one's life. In an allegory, he compared ending one's life, when subject to great suffering, to waking up from sleep when experiencing a terrible nightmare. However, most suicides were seen as an act of the will, as it takes place when one denies life's pains, and is thus different from ascetic renunciation of the will, which denies life's pleasures.[citation needed]

According to Schopenhauer, moral freedom—the highest ethical aim—is to be obtained only by a denial of the will to live. Far from being a denial, suicide is an emphatic assertion of this will. For it is in fleeing from the pleasures, not from the sufferings of life, that this denial consists. When a man destroys his existence as an individual, he is not by any means destroying his will to live. On the contrary, he would like to live if he could do so with satisfaction to himself; if he could assert his will against the power of circumstance; but circumstance is too strong for him.[citation needed]

Schopenhauer also addressed arguments against suicide. "That a man who no longer wishes to live for himself must go on living merely as a machine for others to use is an extravagant demand."[10]

Libertarianism

Libertarianism asserts that a person's life belongs only to them, and no other person has the right to force their own ideals that life must be lived. Rather, only the individual involved can make such a decision, and whatever decision they make should be respected.[citation needed]

Philosopher and psychiatrist Thomas Szasz goes further, arguing that suicide is the most basic right of all. If freedom is self-ownership—ownership over one's own life and body—then the right to end that life is the most basic of all. If others can force you to live, you do not own yourself and belong to them.[11]

Jean Améry, in his book On Suicide: a Discourse on Voluntary Death (originally published in German in 1976), provides a moving insight into the suicidal mind. He argues forcefully and almost romantically that suicide represents the ultimate freedom of humanity, justifying the act with phrases such as "we only arrive at ourselves in a freely chosen death" and lamenting "ridiculously everyday life and its alienation". [citation needed] Améry killed himself in 1978.

Philosophical thinking in the 19th and 20th century has led, in some cases, beyond thinking in terms of pro-choice, to the point that suicide is no longer a last resort, or even something that one must justify, but something that one must justify not doing. Many forms of existentialist thinking essentially begin with the premise that life is objectively meaningless, and proceed to the question of why one should not just kill oneself; they then answer this question by suggesting that the individual has the power to give personal meaning to life.

Stoicism

Although George Lyman Kittredge states that "the Stoics held that suicide is cowardly and wrong," the most famous stoicsSeneca the Younger, Epictetus, and Marcus Aurelius—maintain that death by one's own hand is always an option and frequently more honorable than a life of protracted misery.[12]

The Stoics accepted that suicide was permissible for the wise person in circumstances that might prevent them from living a virtuous life.[13] Plutarch held that accepting life under tyranny would have compromised Cato's self-consistency (Latin: constantia) as a Stoic and impaired his freedom to make the honorable moral choices.[14] Suicide could be justified if one fell victim to severe pain or disease,[13] but otherwise suicide would usually be seen as a rejection of one's social duty.[15]

Confucianism

Confucianism holds that failure to follow certain values is worse than death; hence, suicide can be morally permissible, and even praiseworthy, if it is done for the sake of those values. The Confucian emphasis on loyalty, self-sacrifice, and honour has tended to encourage altruistic suicide.[16] Confucius wrote, "For gentlemen of purpose and men of ren while it is inconceivable that they should seek to stay alive at the expense of ren, it may happen that they have to accept death in order to have ren accomplished."[17] Mencius wrote:[18]

Fish is what I want; bear's palm is also what I want. If I cannot have both, I would rather take bear's palm than fish. Life is what I want; yi is also what I want. If I cannot have both, I would rather take yi than life. On the one hand, though life is what I want, there is something I want more than life. That is why I do not cling to life at all cost. On the other hand, though death is what I loathe, there is something I loathe more than death. That is why there are dangers I do not avoid ... Yet there are ways of remaining alive and ways of avoiding death to which a person will not resort. In other words, there are things a person wants more than life and there are also things he or she loathes more than death.

Other arguments

David Hume wrote an essay entitled Of Suicide[19] in 1755 (although it was not published until the year after his death, in 1777).[20] Most of it is concerned with the claim that suicide is an affront to God. Hume argues that suicide is no more a rebellion against God than is saving the life of someone who would otherwise die, or changing the position of anything in one's surroundings. He spends much less time dismissing arguments that it is an affront to one's duty to others or to oneself. Hume claims that suicide can be compared to retiring from society and becoming a total recluse, which is not normally considered to be immoral. As for duty to self, Hume takes it to be obvious that there can be times when suicide is desirable, though he also thinks it ridiculous that anyone would consider suicide unless they first considered every other option.

Those who support the right to die argue that suicide is acceptable under certain circumstances, such as incurable disease and old age. The idea is that although life is, in general, good, people who face irreversible suffering should not be forced to continue suffering.

Leo Tolstoy wrote in his short work A Confession that after an existential crisis, he considered various options and determined that suicide would be the most logically consistent response in a world where God does not exist. However, he then decided to look less at logic and more towards trying to explain God using a mystical approach in that, for one, he describes God as life. He states that this new understanding of God would allow him to live meaningfully.[21]

Leonard Peikoff states in his book Objectivism: The Philosophy of Ayn Rand:[further explanation needed]

Suicide is justified when man's life, owing to circumstances outside of a person's control, is no longer possible; an example might be a person with a painful terminal illness, or a prisoner in a concentration camp who sees no chance of escape. In cases such as these, suicide is not necessarily a philosophic rejection of life or of reality. On the contrary, it may very well be their tragic reaffirmation. Self-destruction in such contexts may amount to the tortured cry: "Man's life means so much to me that I will not settle for anything less. I will not accept a living death as a substitute."

Bioethicist Jacob Appel has criticized "arbitrary" ethical systems that allow patients to refuse care when they are physically ill, while denying the mentally ill the right to suicide.[22][23]

See also

References

  1. ^ Camus, Albert (1942). The Myth of Sisyphus. Translated by O'Brien, Justin. Penguin Group. ISBN 978-0-141-18200-1.
  2. ^ Tondo, Leonardo (2014), Nemeroff, Charles B.; Ruiz, Pedro; Koslow, Stephen H. (eds.), "Brief history of suicide in Western cultures", A Concise Guide to Understanding Suicide: Epidemiology, Pathophysiology and Prevention, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 3–12, ISBN 978-1-139-51950-2, retrieved 2022-10-16
  3. ^ Paterson, Craig. Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia. Ashgate, 2008.
  4. ^ Sartre analysis of Mersault, in Literary and Philosophical Essays, 1943
  5. ^ Mill, John Stuart (1956). On Liberty. New York: The Liberal Arts Press. p. 125.
  6. ^ Librarian, Archive (2015-05-14). "ARISTOTLE(384-322 B.C.)from Nicomachean Ethics". The Ethics of Suicide Digital Archive. Retrieved 2022-05-05.
  7. ^ Plotin (2022). Le suicide (translation, introduction and commentary by M. Guyot) [On suicide] (in French) (1st ed.). Paris: L'Harmattan. ISBN 978-2-14-030507-8.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  8. ^ Jeremy Bentham, An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation, London, 1789
  9. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur; Saunders, T. Bailey (Thomas Bailey) (1913). Studies in pessimism : a series of essays. University of California Libraries. London: George Allen. p. 43.
  10. ^ Schopenhauer, Arthur; Hollingdale, R. J. (1970). Essays and Aphorisms. London: Penguin Books. p. 148. ISBN 978-0140442274.
  11. ^ Thomas Szasz, Suicide as a Moral Issue
  12. ^ Mark Sacharoff (Jan–Mar 1972), "Suicide and Brutus' Philosophy in Julius Caesar", Journal of the History of Ideas, 33 (1): 115–122, doi:10.2307/2709060, JSTOR 2709060, PMID 11615560
  13. ^ a b Don E. Marietta, (1998), Introduction to ancient philosophy, pages 153–4. Sharpe
  14. ^ Zadorojnyi, Alexei V. (2007). "Cato's suicide in Plutarch AV Zadorojnyi". The Classical Quarterly. 57 (1): 216–230. doi:10.1017/S0009838807000195. S2CID 170834913.
  15. ^ William Braxton Irvine, (2009), A guide to the good life: the ancient art of Stoic joy, page 200. Oxford University Press
  16. ^ Iga, Mamoura; KS Adam (abstract) (1980), "Stress and Suicide in Japan", Transcultural Psychiatric Research Review, 17 (4), Transcultural Psychiatry: 243–244, doi:10.1177/136346158001700405, S2CID 144018059
  17. ^ Analects, trans. D.C. Lau, second edition, (Hong Kong: Chinese University Press, 1992), XV:9D
  18. ^ Mencius, trans. D.C. Lau, (Hong Kong: Chinese University Press, 1984), VI A:10
  19. ^ Hume, David (1777). "Of Suicide". ebooks.adelaide.edu.au. Archived from the original on 21 May 2019. Retrieved 23 November 2019.
  20. ^ "David Hume, 1711-1776". eBooks @ Adelaide. Archived from the original on 6 August 2019. Retrieved 23 November 2019.
  21. ^ Tolstoy, Leo. A Confession (PDF).
  22. ^ Appel, JM. A Suicide Right for the Mentally Ill? A Swiss Case Opens a New Debate, The Hastings Center Report. 2007;37(3):21–23
  23. ^ Wesley J. Smith, Death on Demand: The assisted-suicide movement sheds its fig leaf, The Weekly Standard, June 5, 2007

Further reading

External links

Baca informasi lainnya yang berhubungan dengan : article

Article 19 Article 20

Read other articles:

American firearms manufacturer Advanced Armament CorporationTypePrivateIndustryDefenseFounded1994; 29 years ago (1994)Headquarters1816 Remington CircleHuntsville, Alabama[1]ProductsFirearms, weapons, sound suppressorsParentJJE Capital Holdings, LLC.Websiteadvanced-armament.com Advanced Armament Corporation (AAC) is an American company that develops and manufactures firearms, firearm suppressors, muzzle devices and related accessories. History Kevin Brittingham founded A…

María Irigoyen María Irigoyen nel 2018 Nazionalità  Argentina Altezza 171 cm Peso 63 kg Tennis Termine carriera 2019 Carriera Singolare1 Vittorie/sconfitte 416 - 262 Titoli vinti 0 WTA, 17 ITF Miglior ranking 155º (14 aprile 2014) Risultati nei tornei del Grande Slam  Australian Open Q1 (2011, 2013, 2014, 2015, 2016)  Roland Garros Q1 (2011, 2013, 2014)  Wimbledon Q2 (2010)  US Open Q1 (2012, 2013, 2014, 2015) Doppio1 Vittorie/sconfitte 434 - 191 Titoli vinti 2 WTA, …

Опис файлу Опис Постер фільму Бомж із дробовиком Джерело Час створення 19.12.2019 Автор зображення Ліцензія Це зображення є рекламним плакатом фільму, спортивного або іншого заходу. Найімовірніше, авторськими правами на обкладинку володіє видавець фільму (або студія, що знял

Haus Reinhardtsberg ist ein Weinberghaus im Radebeuler Stadtteil Niederlößnitz in der Oberen Bergstraße 44. Es ist benannt nach dem ehemaligen Besitzer Johann Reinhardt, der das mit Stützmauer und Toreinfahrt denkmalgeschützte[1] Gebäude 1897 erwarb. Das Anwesen liegt im Denkmalschutzgebiet Historische Weinberglandschaft Radebeul.[2] Der Denkmalschutz bestand schon zu DDR-Zeiten. Haus Reinhardtsberg Haus Reinhardtsberg Inhaltsverzeichnis 1 Beschreibung 2 Geschichte 3 Litera…

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (ديسمبر 2019) نيابة غسل الأموال (مصر) تفاصيل الوكالة الحكومية البلد مصر  الإدارة تعديل مصدري - تعديل   نيابة غسل الأموال المصرية هي جهة تحقيق تتبع النائب العام المصري ت…

Liga 3Musim2023–2024TanggalPutaran Provinsi:Juli – Desember 2023Putaran Nasional:Januari – Maret 2024[1]← 2022–2023 2024–2025 → Liga 3 2023 Provinsi Nasional Liga 3 2023–2024 adalah edisi keenam dari musim Liga 3 di bawah nama saat ini dan edisi ketujuh di bawah struktur liga saat ini. Kompetisi ini diselenggarakan oleh Asosiasi Provinsi PSSI untuk putaran provinsi dan PSSI pusat untuk putaran nasional. Tim yang lolos babak 8 besar Liga 3 berhak promosi ke Liga 2 2024–2…

يفتقر محتوى هذه المقالة إلى الاستشهاد بمصادر. فضلاً، ساهم في تطوير هذه المقالة من خلال إضافة مصادر موثوق بها. أي معلومات غير موثقة يمكن التشكيك بها وإزالتها. (يوليو 2017) هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (أ…

Hukum laju atau persamaan laju pada suatu reaksi kimia adalah suatu persamaan yang menghubungkan laju reaksi dengan konsentrasi atau tekanan pada reaktan serta parameter konstannya (biasanya koefisien laju dan orde reaksi parsial).[1] Untuk banyak reaksi laju didefinisikan dengan hukum pemangkatan seperti r = k [ A ] x [ B ] y {\displaystyle r=k[\mathrm {A} ]^{x}[\mathrm {B} ]^{y}} dimana [A] dan [B] menyatakan konsentrasi spesi A dan B, berturut-turut (biasanya dalam mol per liter (mola…

American politician, Civil War Union Army Colonel, Member of the Wisconsin State Senate and Assembly William L. UtleyMember of the Wisconsin Senatefrom the 7th districtIn officeJanuary 9, 1861 – January 4, 1863Preceded byNicholas D. FrattSucceeded byTimothy D. MorrisMember of the Wisconsin State Assemblyfrom the Racine 1st districtIn officeJanuary 8, 1851 – January 12, 1853Preceded byHorace N. ChapmanSucceeded byHorace T. Sanders Personal detailsBornWilliam Lawrence Utley(1…

Infects tomato family, beans, flowers... Tobacco mosaic virus Transmission electron micrograph of TMV particles negative stained to enhance visibility at 160,000× magnification Virus classification (unranked): Virus Realm: Riboviria Kingdom: Orthornavirae Phylum: Kitrinoviricota Class: Alsuviricetes Order: Martellivirales Family: Virgaviridae Genus: Tobamovirus Species: Tobacco mosaic virus Tobacco mosaic virus (TMV) is a positive-sense single-stranded RNA virus species in the genus Tobamovirus…

Three-dimensional chess variant 3D rendering of starting position Millennium 3D chess is a three-dimensional chess variant created by William L. d'Agostino in 2001. It employs three vertically stacked 8×8 boards, with each player controlling a standard set of chess pieces.[1][2] The inventor describes his objective as extending the traditional chess game into a multilevel environment without distorting the basic game.[3] Rules Millennium 3D сhess extends the traditional…

Part of Czechoslovakia between 1969 and 1990 This article includes a list of references, related reading, or external links, but its sources remain unclear because it lacks inline citations. Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations. (April 2021) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) Slovak Socialist Republic (1969–90)Slovenská socialistická republikaSlovak Republic (1990–92)Slovenská republikaFederal subject of the Czechoslovak Socialist Rep…

North African genetic history The genetic history of North Africa encompasses the genetic history of the people of North Africa. The most important source of gene flow to North Africa was from the Middle East, although the Sahara desert to the south and the Mediterranean Sea to the North were also important barriers to gene flow from sub-Saharan Africa and parts of Europe in prehistory. However, North Africa is connected to Western Asia via the Isthmus of Suez and the Sinai peninsula, while at t…

Politics of Minnesota Constitution Executive Governor: Tim Walz (DFL) Lieutenant Governor: Peggy Flanagan (DFL) Secretary of State: Steve Simon (DFL) State Auditor: Julie Blaha (DFL) Attorney General: Keith Ellison (DFL) Cabinet Executive Council Legislature 92nd Legislature Senate President: David Osmek (R) President pro tempore: David Tomassoni (I) Majority leader: Jeremy Miller (R) Minority leader: Melisa Franzen (DFL) House of Representatives Speaker: Melissa Hortman (DFL) Speaker pro tempor…

Viet RockMusicMarianne de PuryBookMegan TerryProductions 1966 La MaMa Experimental Theatre Club 1966 Yale Repertory Theatre 1966 Off-Broadway Viet Rock is a rock musical by Megan Terry that served as inspiration to the musical Hair. A violent denunciation of the American involvement in the Vietnam War, the play was described by its author as a folk war movie comprising scenes of disillusionment and protest to the American military presence in Southeast Asia.[1] Viet Rock is widely consid…

British television series This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Gamer.tv – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (September 2009) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) Gamer.tvThe Gamer.tv logoCreated byIMGStarringSam DelaneyCountry of originUnited KingdomNo. of episodes283Product…

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (سبتمبر 2022) اشتمل التطور السياسي لجورج واشنطن على تحول شاب من أسرة متوسطة الغنى في مستعمرة فيرجينيا البريطانية مدفوعًا بصورة رئيسية بمصلحته الذاتية إلى أول رئيس للولاي…

A woman in Yetebon Yetebon is a small village in the former Meskanena Mareko woreda of Ethiopia. The village is located 9 kilometres (5.6 mi) from Butajira, and is about a two-hour drive south of Addis Ababa, and is 75 miles (121 km) south of Addis Ababa. Yetebon is the home of the Gurage people who are tradesmen, herdsmen, and farmers. Guraghes live in tukuls, which are circular mud and wattle structures with tall thatched roofs and generally no windows. They stand in small clusters, …

Thraki redirects here. For ships named Thraki, see SS Thraki. Traditional region of GreeceThrace ΘράκηTraditional region of GreeceThrace (blue) within GreeceCession1920Replaced as administrative region by Eastern Macedonia and Thrace1987CapitalKomotiniRegional units List XanthiRhodopeEvros Government • Deputy MinisterStavros Kalafatis [el] (New Democracy)Area • Total8,578 km2 (3,312 sq mi)Population • Total371,208(2011 census)&…

15th Parliament of Malaysia ←14th Parliament 16th Parliament→OverviewLegislative bodyParliament of MalaysiaJurisdictionMalaysiaMeeting placeMalaysian Houses of ParliamentElectionIndirect election and appointmentsWebsitewww.parlimen.gov.myDewan NegaraMembers70PresidentWan Junaidi Tuanku JaafarDeputy PresidentNur Jazlan MohamedSecretaryMuhammad Sujairi AbdullahParty controlBarisan NasionalPakatan HarapanGabungan Parti SarawakGabungan Rakyat SabahSovereignYang di-Pertuan AgongAbdullah o…

Kembali kehalaman sebelumnya