After Virtue

After Virtue
Cover of the first edition
AuthorAlasdair MacIntyre
SubjectEthics
Published1981 (University of Notre Dame Press)
ISBN978-0-268-00594-8

After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory is a book on moral philosophy by the Scottish philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre. MacIntyre provides a bleak view of the state of modern moral discourse, regarding it as failing to be rational, and failing to admit to being irrational. He claims that older forms of moral discourse were in better shape, particularly singling out Aristotle's moral philosophy as an exemplar. After Virtue is among the most important texts in the recent revival of virtue ethics.

The book was first published in 1981 and has since gone through two subsequent editions, which have added to, but not changed, the original text. The second edition, published in 1984, adds a postscript replying to critics of the first edition; the third edition, published in 2007, contains a new prologue entitled "After Virtue After a Quarter of a Century".

Summary

MacIntyre holds that After Virtue makes seven central claims.[1] It begins with an allegory suggestive of the premise of the science-fiction novel A Canticle for Leibowitz: a world where all sciences have been dismantled quickly and almost entirely. MacIntyre asks what the sciences would look like if they were re-assembled from the remnants of scientific knowledge that survived the catastrophe.

He claims that the new sciences, though superficially similar to the old, would in fact be devoid of real scientific content, because the key suppositions and attitudes would not be present. "The hypothesis which I wish to advance", he continues, "is that in the actual world which we inhabit the language of morality is in the same state of grave disorder as the language of natural science in the imaginary world which I described."[2] Specifically, MacIntyre applies this hypothesis to advance the notion that the moral structures that emerged from the Enlightenment were philosophically doomed from the start because they were formed using the aforementioned incoherent language of morality. MacIntyre claims that this failure encompasses the work of many significant Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment moral philosophers, including Søren Kierkegaard, Karl Marx, Immanuel Kant, and David Hume. These philosophers "fail because of certain shared characteristics deriving from their highly specific historical background."[3] That background is the Enlightenment's abandonment of Aristotelianism, and in particular the Aristotelian concept of teleology.

Ancient and medieval ethics, argues MacIntyre, relied wholly on the teleological idea that human life had a proper end or character, and that human beings could not reach this natural end without preparation. Renaissance science rejected Aristotle's teleological physics as an incorrect and unnecessary account, which led Renaissance philosophy to make a similar rejection in the realm of ethics. But shorn of teleology, ethics as a body of knowledge was expurgated of its central content, and only remained as, essentially, a vocabulary list with few definitions and no context. With such an incomplete framework on which to base their moral understanding, the philosophers of the Enlightenment and their successors were doomed from the beginning.

MacIntyre illustrates this point through an example of a people who, he argues, experienced a similar incoherence in their own moral and ethical tradition: the Polynesian people of the South Pacific and their taboos. King Kamehameha II removed the taboos of the people in order to modernize their society and met little if any resistance. The Polynesians had no issue with abandoning their long-standing cultural traditions and MacIntyre claims this is because the taboos, though once meaningful to the islanders, had been shorn over the centuries of their underlying spiritual and didactic purpose, becoming a set of arbitrary prohibitions. The fact that Kamehameha II could abolish them so easily and without opposition is evidence, MacIntyre argues, of their incoherence. A similar incoherence, he argues, bedevils the ethical project since the Enlightenment.

Another reason MacIntyre gives for the doomed nature of the Enlightenment is the fact that it ascribed moral agency to the individual. He claims this made morality no more than one man's opinion and, thus, philosophy became a forum of inexplicably subjective rules and principles. The failure of the Enlightenment Project, because of the abandonment of a teleological structure, is shown by the inadequacy of moral emotivism, which MacIntyre believes accurately reflects the state of modern morality.

MacIntyre offers a critique of Friedrich Nietzsche, whom he calls the "King Kamehameha II of the European tradition," in reference to the Polynesian allegory above.[4] MacIntyre explains that, "Nietzschean man, the Übermensch, [is] the man who transcends, finds his good nowhere in the social world to date, but only that in himself which dictates his own new law and his own new table of the virtues."[5] Although he disagreed with Nietzsche's inegalitarian and elitist view of humankind, he acknowledged the validity of Nietzsche's critique of Enlightenment morality as an explanation of the latter's degeneration into emotivism, and that, like Kamehameha II, Nietzsche had identified the moral imperatives of his time as arbitrary and incoherent in demanding their abolition.

The nineteenth-century critic who has most lastingly and profoundly influenced MacIntyre is not Nietzsche but Marx—indeed, After Virtue originates in MacIntyre's plans to write a book repairing the moral weaknesses of Marxism.[6] His critique of capitalism, and its associated liberal ideology and bureaucratic state (including what, in After Virtue, he condemned as the state capitalism of the USSR) is not expressed in traditional Marxist terms. Instead, it is written as a defence of ordinary social "practices", and of the "goods internal to practices". Pursuit of these helps to give narrative structure and intelligibility to our lives, but these goods must be defended against their corruption by "institutions", which pursue such "external goods" as money, power and status (chapters 14–15).

MacIntyre seeks to find an alternative to Nietzsche's philosophy and eventually concludes that only classic Aristotelian thought can hope to save Western humanity. While Nietzsche seems to include the Aristotelian ethics and politics in his attack on the "degenerate disguises of the will to power,"[7] MacIntyre claims that this cannot be done due to important differences between the structure and assumptions of Aristotelian and post-Enlightenment philosophy. These include:

  • Aristotle's assumption that man is as-he-happens-to-be and that this is distinct from man-as-he-should-be. The Enlightenment, on the other hand, offers no metaphysical framework whatsoever in place of teleology.
  • Aristotle's claim that rules are based on virtues, which are derived from an understanding of the telos. The Enlightenment reversed this and predicated virtues on an understanding of subjective (but purported to be universal) principles.
  • Aristotle's assertion that virtue and morality are integral parts of society, as an understanding of the telos must be social and not individual. In the Enlightenment, however, societies lost their moral authority and the individual became the fundamental interpreter of moral questions.

MacIntyre opposes Nietzsche's return to the aristocratic ethics of Homeric Greece with the teleological approach to ethics pioneered by Aristotle. Nietzsche's critique of Enlightenment moral theory does not work against a teleological ethics. For MacIntyre, "Nietzsche replaces the fictions of the Enlightenment individualism, of which he is so contemptuous, with a set of individualist fictions of his own."[8] Nietzsche's Übermensch, his solution to the lies of the Enlightenment, exposes the failure of the Enlightenment's epistemological project and of its search for a subjective yet universal morality. Nietzsche neglects the role of society in the formation and understanding of tradition and morality, and "Nietzsche's great man cannot enter into relationships mediated by appeal to shared standards or virtues or goods; he is his own only moral authority and his relationships to others have to be exercises of that authority... it will be to condemn oneself to that moral solipsism which constitutes Nietzschean greatness."[9]

After Virtue ends by posing the question 'Nietzsche or Aristotle?', although MacIntyre acknowledges that the book does not give sufficient grounds for a definitive answer that it is Aristotle, not Nietzsche, who points to the best solution for the problems that the book has diagnosed. Those grounds are set out in MacIntyre's subsequent works, in which he elaborates a sophisticated revision of the philosophical tradition of Aristotelianism.

In the end, however, MacIntyre tells us that we are waiting not for Godot but for Benedict of Nursia. MacIntyre criticizes individualist political philosophy, such as John Rawls' A Theory of Justice and Robert Nozick's Anarchy, State, and Utopia. To MacIntyre, morals and virtues can only be comprehended through their relation to the community which they come from. Whereas Rawls tells us to conceive of justice through abstracting ourselves from who we are (through the veil of ignorance, for example) MacIntyre disagrees. Running throughout After Virtue is the belief that in order to comprehend who we are, we must understand where we come from.

Reception

The critic George Scialabba found After Virtue to be a strong critique of modernity, but claimed that MacIntyre "faltered" at the conclusion of the argument, when he sketched the features of what virtuous life should be like in the conditions of modernity. In particular, Scialabba objected to MacIntyre's claim that the good life for human beings consists in contemplating the good life for human beings; Scialabba found this insufficient and anticlimactic. Scialabba also argued that, although he appreciated MacIntyre's insistence on participation in community life as the best defense against the perils of modernity, this insistence was not justified with any discussion of how community life can be reconciled with the critical spirit that Scialabba finds to be one of the great achievements of modernity and of the philosophical enterprise.[10]

In a review for Political Theory, William E. Connolly argues that MacIntyre sees Nietzsche as "the adversary to be defeated, but Nietzsche's voice is not heard clearly."[11] Connolly objects that MacIntyre's defense of virtue does not take into account Nietzsche's critique; MacIntyre also fails to build an account of telos that does not draw on biology in the way MacIntyre wanted to avoid—such a theory does not account for the fact that we are embodied.[12]

Anthony Ellis, in the journal Philosophy, argued that MacIntyre's positive philosophical project is not explained as well as it could have been: it is "of daunting opacity, though tantalizingly interesting" but not given enough space in the book.[13] Ellis also states that the discussion of Rawls and Nozick in After Virtue "is slight and assertive".[14]

In the Review of Metaphysics, Christos Evangeliou said that if the reader "had expected to find in this book concretely how a revived Aristotelian tradition is supposed to work in order to shape ethically and rationally the irrational and disorderly modern world", they "may be a little disappointed in their expectations".[15]

See also

References

Footnotes

  1. ^ MacIntyre 1998, pp. 69–72.
  2. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 2.
  3. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 51.
  4. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 113.
  5. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 257.
  6. ^ MacIntyre 1984, pp. ix–x.
  7. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 127.
  8. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 129.
  9. ^ MacIntyre 1984, p. 258.
  10. ^ George Scialabba's review of After Virtue
  11. ^ Connolly 1982, p. 317.
  12. ^ Connolly 1982.
  13. ^ Ellis 1982.
  14. ^ Ellis 1982, p. 553.
  15. ^ Evangeliou 1983, p. 134.

Bibliography

  • Connolly, William E. (1982). "Review of After Virtue, by Alasdair MacIntyre". Political Theory. 10 (2): 315–319. doi:10.1177/0090591782010002010.
  • Ellis, Anthony (1982). "Review of After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, by Alasdair MacIntyre". Philosophy. 57 (222): 551–553. JSTOR 4619611.
  • Evangeliou, Christos (1983). "Review of After Virtue, by A. MacIntyre". The Review of Metaphysics. 37 (1): 132–134. JSTOR 20127983.
  • MacIntyre, Alasdair (1984). After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (2nd ed.). Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.
  •  ———  (1998). "The Claims of After Virtue". In Knight, Kelvin (ed.). The MacIntyre Reader. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press.

Read other articles:

Rumah Tjong A Fie張阿輝 故居Fasade rumahInformasi umumGaya arsitekturArsitektur PeranakanKotaMedanSumatera UtaraNegaraIndonesiaRampung1900 Cagar budaya IndonesiaRumah Tjong A FiePeringkatNasionalKategoriBangunanNo. RegnasCB.81LokasikeberadaanKota Medan, Sumatera UtaraNo. SK246/M/2015Tanggal SK21 Desember 2015Tingkat SKMenteriPemilikKeluarga Tjong A FiePengelolaKeluarga Tjong A FieKoordinat3°35′08″N 98°40′50″E / 3.5855204°N 98.6804873°E / 3.5855204; 98....

 

Fictional character Fictional character William BludworthFinal Destination characterTony Todd as William Bludworth, as depicted in Final Destination 5First appearanceFinal DestinationLast appearanceFinal Destination 5Created byJeffrey ReddickPortrayed byTony ToddIn-universe informationOccupationCoronerLocationMt. Abraham, New York North Bay, New YorkStatusAlive William Bludworth is a fictional character in the Final Destination film series, portrayed by Tony Todd. He appears in Final Destinat...

 

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (أغسطس 2023) يفتقر محتوى هذه المقالة إلى الاستشهاد بمصادر. فضلاً، ساهم في تطوير هذه المقالة من خلال إضافة مصادر موثوق بها. أي معلومات غير موثقة يمكن التشكيك بها وإزالتها. ...

The following is an incomplete list of known planetary nebulae. Messier Catalogue[a] NGC[a] Otherdesignation[a] Datediscovered[a] Distance(kly)[a][b] Apparentmagnitude(visual)[a] Constellation[a] Glowing Eye Nebulaor Dandelion Puffball Nebula NGC 6751 1863 6.5 11.9 Aquila Turtle Nebula NGC 6210 1825 4.7 9.3 Hercules Bow-Tie Nebula NGC 40 Caldwell 2 1788 3.5 11.4 Cepheus Ghost of Jupiter NGC 3242 1785 1.4 8.6 Hydra Blinking Planet...

 

Telephone numbers in SerbiaLocation of SerbiaLocationCountrySerbiaContinentEuropeRegulatorRATELTypeOpenFormat0xx xxx xx xxAccess codesCountry code+381International access00Long-distance0 Regulation of the telephone numbers in Serbia is under the responsibility of the Regulatory Agency of Electronic Communication and Mail Services (RATEL), independent from the government.[1] The country calling code of Serbia is +381. The country has an open telephone numbering plan, with most numbers ...

 

هذه المقالة يتيمة إذ تصل إليها مقالات أخرى قليلة جدًا. فضلًا، ساعد بإضافة وصلة إليها في مقالات متعلقة بها. (مارس 2023) سكيليتون (بالإنجليزية: Skelton)‏ معلومات شخصية مكان الميلاد عالم ماينكرافت الإقامة عالم ماينكرافت الحياة العملية أول ظهور ماينكرافت (2009) المبتكر ماركوس بيرسون ا...

Costa Rican footballer (born 1985) In this Spanish name, the first or paternal surname is Granados and the second or maternal family name is Maroto. Esteban Granados Granados with Costa Rica at the 2014 FIFA World CupPersonal informationFull name Óscar Esteban Granados MarotoDate of birth (1985-10-25) 25 October 1985 (age 38)Place of birth Cartago, Costa RicaHeight 1.83 m (6 ft 0 in)Position(s) Defensive midfielderYouth career CartaginésSenior career*Years Team A...

 

American singer and songwriter (born 1987) For other uses, see Kesha (disambiguation). Not to be confused with Keisha. KeshaKesha in 2022BornKesha Rose Sebert (1987-03-01) March 1, 1987 (age 36)Los Angeles, California, U.S.Other namesKe$haOccupationsSingersongwriterYears active2005–presentWorksDiscographysongsvideographyParentPebe Sebert (mother)AwardsFull listMusical careerGenresElectropopdance-popsynth-poppop rockpop rapInstrument(s)VocalsguitarpianokeyboardssynthesizerLabe...

 

Area in NorwayGulskogenAreaCoordinates: 59°44′45″N 10°09′51″E / 59.7457°N 10.1641°E / 59.7457; 10.1641VikenNorwayTime zoneUTC+01:00 (CET) Fra GulskogenPeter Nicolai Arbo (1871) Gulskogen is a borough in Drammen, Viken, Norway. Gulskogen has a population of 3,856 inhabitants (2005). Strømsgodset was the name of the parish from early times. Strømsgodset was a separate municipality which in 1964 became part of Drammen. The district takes its name from the hi...

Sri Lankan statesman This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Oliver Goonetilleke – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (April 2015) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) His ExcellencySir Oliver GoonetillekeGCMG KCVO KBE KStJ3rd Governor-General of CeylonIn offi...

 

1908 play by French playwright Alexandre Bisson For other uses, see Madame X (disambiguation). First edition of the novel adaptation by J. W. McConaughy illustrated by Edward Charles Volkert Madame X (original title La Femme X) is a 1908 play by French playwright Alexandre Bisson (1848–1912). It was novelized in English and adapted for the American stage; it was also adapted for the screen twelve times over sixty-five years, including versions in Tagalog, Greek, and Spanish as well as E...

 

Band discography Guano Apes discographyGuano Apes live at Bospop (2009)Studio albums5Live albums1Compilation albums2Video albums5Music videos20Singles18 Guano Apes are an alternative rock band formed in 1994 in Göttingen, Germany. The group members are Sandra Nasić (vocals), Henning Rümenapp (guitars, backing vocals), Stefan Ude (bass, backing vocals) and Dennis Poschwatta (drums, backing vocals).[1] Their sound has been described as a fusion of metal, pop and rap.[1] Usual...

1990 American television dramatic film The Last Best YearGenreDramaWritten byDavid W. RintelsDirected byJohn ErmanStarringMary Tyler MooreBernadette PetersCarmen MatthewsKate ReidKenneth WelshErika AlexanderDorothy McGuireMusic byJohn MorrisOriginal languageEnglishProductionExecutive producerVictoria RiskinProducersJohn ErmanJosette PerrottaDavid W. RintelsProduction locationsTorontoChicagoCinematographyFrank TidyEditorPaul LaMastraRunning time96 minutesProduction companiesDavid W. Rintels Pr...

 

Gaunpalika in Gandaki, NepalRishing Rural Municipality ऋषिङ्ग गाउँपालिकाGaunpalikaRishing Rural MunicipalityLocation in NepalCoordinates: 27°55′20″N 84°10′40″E / 27.922313°N 84.177882°E / 27.922313; 84.177882Country   NepalProvinceGandakiDistrictTanahun DistrictGovernment • ChairpersonRajendra Krishna ShresthaPopulation • Total25,870Time zoneUTC+5:45 (Nepal Time)Websitehttp://rishingmun....

 

This is a historical list of all bishops of the Catholic Church whose sees were within the present-day boundaries of the United States, with links to the bishops who consecrated them. It includes only members of the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops and their predecessors. The number references the sequence of consecration. Diocese refers to the diocese over which the bishop presided or, if he did not preside, the diocese in which he served as coadjutor bishop or auxiliary bishop. ...

American skeptic, paranormal investigator James UnderdownBorn (1960-10-09) October 9, 1960 (age 63)Chicago, Illinois, United StatesNationalityAmericanEducationB.A. in EnglishAlma materDePauw UniversityOccupation(s)Executive Director of CFI Los Angeles, Founder of IIG James Underdown's Voice Recorded in February 2014 Problems playing this file? See media help. WebsiteCenter for Inquiry Investigations Group, Center for Inquiry,UFOTOS James Jim Underdown (born October 9, 1960) has been...

 

2013 Indian filmLokpalTheatrical release posterDirected byJoshiyWritten byS. N. SwamyProduced byRuby VijayanS. L. Vimal KumarStarring Mohanlal Kavya Madhavan Meera Nandan Manoj K. Jayan Thambi Ramaiah Sai Kumar CinematographyPradeep NairEdited byShyam SasidharanMusic byRatheesh VeghaProductioncompanyHappy & Ruby CinemasDistributed byMaxlab Cinemas and EntertainmentsRelease date 31 January 2013 (2013-01-31) [1][2][3]Running time140 minutesCountryIndia...

 

American artist This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these template messages) A major contributor to this article appears to have a close connection with its subject. It may require cleanup to comply with Wikipedia's content policies, particularly neutral point of view. Please discuss further on the talk page. (August 2020) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) This article is an orphan,...

e-Prix de Ciudad de México de 20182018 FIA Formula E Ciudad de México ePrix FIA Fórmula E Trazado utilizado para el e-Prix de 2018Datos generalesSede Autódromo Hermanos Rodríguez, Ciudad de MéxicoMéxico MéxicoFecha 3 de marzo de 2018Edición IIICircuitoTipo y longitud Instalaciones permanentes2,092Distancia total 47 vueltas 98,324ResultadosPole positionPiloto  Felix RosenqvistMahindra RacingTiempo 1:01.645PodioPrimero Daniel AbtSegundo Oliver TurveyTercero Sébastien BuemiVuelta ...

 

4th Reconnaissance Battalion4th Reconnaissance Battalion insigniaActive1 July 1962 – presentCountry United States of AmericaBranch United States Marine CorpsType Marine Division ReconPart of Marine Forces Reserve 4th Marine DivisionGarrison/HQNavy Reserve Center San Antonio, San Antonio, TXPatron Major Anthony Cold Steel WalkerEngagementsWorld War II Battle of Kwajalein Battle of Saipan Battle of Tinian Battle of Iwo Jima Operation Desert StormOperation Iraqi FreedomCommander...

 

Strategi Solo vs Squad di Free Fire: Cara Menang Mudah!