The theorem is named after Georg Cantor, who first published it in 1895, using it to characterize the (uncountable) ordering on the real numbers. It can be proved by a back-and-forth method that is also sometimes attributed to Cantor but was actually published later, by Felix Hausdorff. The same back-and-forth method also proves that countable dense unbounded orders are highly symmetric, and can be applied to other kinds of structures. However, Cantor's original proof only used the "going forth" half of this method. In terms of model theory, the isomorphism theorem can be expressed by saying that the first-order theory of unbounded dense linear orders is countably categorical, meaning that it has only one countable model, up to logical equivalence.
One application of Cantor's isomorphism theorem involves temporal logic, a method for using logic to reason about time. In this application, the theorem implies that it is sufficient to use intervals of rational numbers to model intervals of time: using irrational numbers for this purpose will not lead to any increase in logical power.
Statement and examples
Cantor's isomorphism theorem is stated using the following concepts:
A linear order or total order is defined by a set of elements and a comparison operation that gives an ordering to each pair of distinct elements and obeys the transitive law.[1][2] The familiar numeric orderings on the integers, rational numbers, and real numbers are all examples of linear orders.[2]
Unboundedness means that the ordering does not contain a minimum or maximum element. This is different from the concept of a bounded set in a metric space. For instance, the open interval (0,1) is unbounded as an ordered set, even though it is bounded as a subset of the real numbers, because neither its infimum 0 nor its supremum 1 belong to the interval.[1] The integers, rationals, and reals are also unbounded.[2]
An ordering is dense when every pair of elements has another element between them.[1] This is different from being a topologically dense set within the real numbers.[2] The rational numbers and real numbers are dense in this sense, as the arithmetic mean of any two numbers belongs to the same set and lies between them, but the integers are not dense because is no other integer between any two consecutive integers.[3]
Two linear orders are order-isomorphic when there exists a one-to-one correspondence between them that preserves their ordering.[1][2] For instance, the integers and the even numbers are order-isomorphic, under a bijection that multiplies each integer by two.[3]
With these definitions in hand, Cantor's isomorphism theorem states that every two unbounded countable dense linear orders are order-isomorphic.[1]
Within the rational numbers, certain subsets are also countable, unbounded, and dense. The rational numbers in the open unit interval are an example. Another example is the set of dyadic rational numbers, the numbers that can be expressed as a fraction with an integer numerator and a power of two as the denominator. By Cantor's isomorphism theorem, the dyadic rational numbers are order-isomorphic to the whole set of rational numbers. In this example, an explicit order isomorphism is provided by Minkowski's question-mark function.[4] Another example of a countable unbounded dense linear order is given by the set of real algebraic numbers, the real roots of polynomials with integer coefficients. In this case, they are a superset of the rational numbers, but are again order-isomorphic.[5] It is also possible to apply the theorem to other linear orders whose elements are not defined as numbers. For instance, the binary strings that end in a 1, in their lexicographic order, form another isomorphic ordering.[6]
Proofs
One proof of Cantor's isomorphism theorem, in some sources called "the standard proof",[7] uses the back-and-forth method. This proof builds up an isomorphism between any two given orders, using a greedy algorithm, in an ordering given by a countable enumeration of the two orderings. In more detail, the proof maintains two order-isomorphic finite subsets and of the two given orders, initially empty. It repeatedly increases the sizes of and by adding a new element from one order, the first missing element in its enumeration, and matching it with an order-equivalent element of the other order, proven to exist using the density and lack of endpoints of the order. The two orderings switch roles at each step: the proof finds the first missing element of the first order, adds it to , matches it with an element of the second order, and adds it to ; then it finds the first missing element of the second order, adds it to , matches it with an element of the first order, and adds it to , etc. Every element of each ordering is eventually matched with an order-equivalent element of the other ordering, so the two orderings are isomorphic.[8]
Although the back-and-forth method has also been attributed to Cantor, Cantor's original publication of this theorem in 1895–1897 used a different proof.[8] In an investigation of the history of this theorem by logician Charles L. Silver, the earliest instance of the back-and-forth proof found by Silver was in a 1914 textbook by Felix Hausdorff, his Grundzüge der Mengenlehre.[8]
Instead of building up order-isomorphic subsets and by going "back and forth" between the enumeration for the first order and the enumeration for the second order, Cantor's original proof only uses the "going forth" half of the back-and-forth method.[1] It repeatedly augments the two finite sets and by adding to the first missing element of the first order's enumeration, and adding to the order-equivalent element that is first in the second order's enumeration. This naturally finds an equivalence between the first ordering and a subset of the second ordering, and Cantor then argues that the entire second ordering is included.[1][8]
The back-and-forth proof has been formalized as a computer-verified proof using Coq, an interactive theorem prover. This formalization process led to a strengthened result that when two computably enumerable linear orders have a computable comparison predicate, and computable functions representing their density and unboundedness properties, then the isomorphism between them is also computable.[9]
Model theory
One way of describing Cantor's isomorphism theorem uses the language of model theory. The first-order theory of unbounded dense linear orders consists of sentences in mathematical logic concerning variables that represent the elements of an order, with a binary relation used as the comparison operation of the ordering. Here, a sentence means a well-formed formula that has no free variables. These sentences include both axioms, formulating in logical terms the requirements of a dense linear order, and all other sentences that can be proven as logical consequences from those axioms. The axioms of this system can be expressed as:[10][11]
Axiom
Explanation
Comparison is irreflexive: no element is less than itself.
Comparison is connected or total, meaning every two distinct elements are comparable.
Comparison is transitive: each triple of elements is consistently ordered.
There is no lower bound; every element has a smaller element .
There is no upper bound; every element has a larger element .
The order is dense: every two elements and have an element between them.
A model of this theory is any system of elements and a comparison relation that obeys all of the axioms; it is a countable model when the system of elements forms a countable set. For instance, the usual comparison relation on the rational numbers is a countable model of this theory. Cantor's isomorphism theorem can be expressed by saying that the first-order theory of unbounded dense linear orders is countably categorical: it has only one countable model, up to logical equivalence.[1][12] However, it is not categorical for higher cardinalities: for any higher cardinality, there are multiple inequivalent dense unbounded linear orders with the same cardinality.[13]
A method of quantifier elimination in the first-order theory of unbounded dense linear orders can be used to prove that it is a complete theory. This means that every logical sentence in the language of this theory is either a theorem, that is, provable as a logical consequence of the axioms, or the negation of a theorem. This is closely related to being categorical (a sentence is a theorem if it is true of the unique countable model; see the Łoś–Vaught test) but there can exist multiple distinct models that have the same complete theory. In particular, both the ordering on the rational numbers and the ordering on the real numbers are models of the same theory, even though they are different models. Quantifier elimination can also be used in an algorithm for deciding whether a given sentence is a theorem.[11]
Related results
The same back-and-forth method used to prove Cantor's isomorphism theorem also proves that countable dense linear orders are highly symmetric. Their symmetries are called order automorphisms, and consist of order-preserving bijections from the whole linear order to itself. By the back-and-forth method, every countable dense linear order has order automorphisms that map any set of points to any other set of points. This can also be proven directly for the ordering on the rationals, by constructing a piecewise linear order automorphism with breakpoints at the given points. This equivalence of all -element sets of points is summarized by saying that the group of symmetries of a countable dense linear order is "highly homogeneous". However, there is no order automorphism that maps an ordered pair of points to its reverse, so these symmetries do not form a 2-transitive group.[1]
The isomorphism theorem can be extended to colorings of an unbounded dense countable linear ordering, with a finite or countable set of colors, such that each color is dense, in the sense that a point of that color exists between any other two points of the whole ordering. The subsets of points with each color partition the order into a family of unbounded dense countable linear orderings. Any partition of an unbounded dense countable linear orderings into subsets, with the property that each subset is unbounded (within the whole set, not just in itself) and dense (again, within the whole set) comes from a coloring in this way. Each two colorings with the same number of colors are order-isomorphic, under any permutation of their colors. Bhattacharjee et al. (1997) give as an example the partition of the rational numbers into the dyadic rationals and their complement; these two sets are dense in each other, and their union has an order isomorphism to any other pair of unbounded linear orders that are countable and dense in each other. Unlike Cantor's isomorphism theorem, the proof needs the full back-and-forth argument, and not just the "going forth" argument.[1]
Cantor used the isomorphism theorem to characterize the ordering of the real numbers, an uncountable set. Unlike the rational numbers, the real numbers are Dedekind-complete, meaning that every subset of the reals that has a finite upper bound has a real least upper bound. They contain the rational numbers, which are dense in the real numbers. By applying the isomorphism theorem, Cantor proved that whenever a linear ordering has the same properties of being Dedekind-complete and containing a countable dense unbounded subset, it must be order-isomorphic to the real numbers.[14]Suslin's problem asks whether orders having certain other properties of the order on the real numbers, including unboundedness, density, and completeness, must be order-isomorphic to the reals; the truth of this statement is independent of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice(ZFC).[15]
Although uncountable unbounded dense orderings may not be order-isomorphic, it follows from the back-and-forth method that any two such orderings are elementarily equivalent.[7][16] Another consequence of Cantor's proof is that every finite or countable linear order can be embedded into the rationals, or into any unbounded dense ordering. Calling this a "well known" result of Cantor, Wacław Sierpiński proved an analogous result for higher cardinality: assuming the continuum hypothesis, there exists a linear ordering of cardinality into which all other linear orderings of cardinality can be embedded.[17]Baumgartner's axiom, formulated by James Earl Baumgartner in 1973 to study the continuum hypothesis, concerns -dense sets of real numbers, unbounded sets with the property that every two elements are separated by exactly other elements. It states that each two such sets are order-isomorphic, providing in this way another higher-cardinality analogue of Cantor's isomorphism theorem ( is defined as the cardinality of the set of all countable ordinals). Baumgartner's axiom is consistent with ZFC and the negation of the continuum hypothesis, and implied by the proper forcing axiom,[18] but independent of Martin's axiom.[19]
In temporal logic, various formalizations of the concept of an interval of time can be shown to be equivalent to defining an interval by a pair of distinct elements of a dense unbounded linear order. This connection implies that these theories are also countably categorical, and can be uniquely modeled by intervals of rational numbers.[20][21]
Sierpiński's theorem stating that any two countable metric spaces without isolated points are homeomorphic can be seen as a topological analogue of Cantor's isomorphism theorem, and can be proved using a similar back-and-forth argument.
^ abBryant, Ross (2006), A computation of partial isomorphism rank on ordinal structures (Doctoral dissertation), University of North Texas, p. 1, 305292986
^Kirst, Dominik (2022), "Computational back-and-forth arguments in constructive type theory", in Andronick, June; de Moura, Leonardo (eds.), 13th International Conference on Interactive Theorem Proving, ITP 2022, August 7–10, 2022, Haifa, Israel, LIPIcs, vol. 237, Schloss Dagstuhl – Leibniz-Zentrum für Informatik, pp. 22:1–22:12, doi:10.4230/LIPIcs.ITP.2022.22
^For this axiomatization of strict linear orders, see: Goldrei, Derek (2005), Propositional and Predicate Calculus: A Model of Argument, Springer, p. 193, ISBN9781846282294. The axioms can be formulated logically using either a strict comparison or a non-strict comparison but the strict comparison simplifies the expression of the axioms for the properties of being unbounded and dense. Note that it is not necessary to specify that these orders are antisymmetric, that is, that ; this is a consequence of irreflexivity and transitivity.
^ abWorrell, James (2016), "Decidable theories"(PDF), Logic and Proof (Lecture notes), University of Oxford; Worrell uses a different but equivalent axiomatization for strict linear orders, and combines the two unboundedness axioms into a single axiom.
^Büchi, J. Richard; Danhof, Kenneth J. (1973), "Variations on a theme of Cantor in the theory of relational structures", Zeitschrift für Mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, 19 (26–29): 411–426, doi:10.1002/malq.19730192604, MR0337567
^Devlin, Keith J.; Johnsbråten, Håvard (1974), The Souslin problem, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 405, Berlin & New York: Springer-Verlag, MR0384542
^Langford, C. H. (1926–1927), "Some theorems on deducibility", Annals of Mathematics, Second Series, 28 (1–4): 16–40, doi:10.2307/1968352, JSTOR1968352, MR1502760
^Ladkin, Peter B. (1987), "Models of axioms for time intervals", in Forbus, Kenneth D.; Shrobe, Howard E. (eds.), Proceedings of the 6th National Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Seattle, WA, USA, July 1987, Morgan Kaufmann, pp. 234–239
Wahyu 17Wahyu 13:16-14:4 yang tertulis pada fragmen Papirus 47 dari abad ke-3 M.KitabKitab WahyuKategoriApokalipsBagian Alkitab KristenPerjanjian BaruUrutan dalamKitab Kristen27← pasal 16 pasal 18 → Wahyu 17 (disingkat Why 17) adalah pasal ketujuh belas Wahyu kepada Yohanes, kitab terakhir dalam Perjanjian Baru di Alkitab Kristen.[1][2] Pengarangnya diyakini adalah Yohanes bin Zebedeus, seorang dari Keduabelas Rasul Yesus Kristus.[3][4][5] T...
Food and drink: Desserts Template‑class Food portalThis template is within the scope of WikiProject Food and drink, a collaborative effort to improve the coverage of food and drink related articles on Wikipedia. If you would like to participate, please visit the project page, where you can join the discussion and see a list of open tasks.Food and drinkWikipedia:WikiProject Food and drinkTemplate:WikiProject Food and drinkFood and drink articlesTemplateThis template does not require a rating...
Титульна сторінка екземпляра «Малого коментаря» з Австрійської національної бібліотеки «Малий коментар Миколая Коперника до гіпотез руху небесних тіл, висунутих ним самим» (лат. Nicolai Copernici de hypothesibus motuum coelestium a se constitutis commentariolus, часто коротко називається «Commentariolus», тобто �...
اضغط هنا للاطلاع على كيفية قراءة التصنيف غزال المهرّ حالة الحفظ أنواع مهددة بالانقراض (خطر انقراض أقصى)[1] المرتبة التصنيفية نوع[2] التصنيف العلمي النطاق: حقيقيات النوى المملكة: الحيوانات الشعبة: الحبليات الطائفة: الثدييات الرتبة: مزدوجات الأصابع الفصيلة: البقريا
Labuhanbatu beralih ke halaman ini. Untuk kegunaan lain, lihat Labuhanbatu (disambiguasi). Kabupaten LabuhanbatuKabupatenTranskripsi bahasa daerah • Abjad Jawiلابهان بتو LambangMotto: Ika bina en paboloItu dibangun, itu diperbaikiPetaKabupaten LabuhanbatuPetaTampilkan peta SumatraKabupaten LabuhanbatuKabupaten Labuhanbatu (Indonesia)Tampilkan peta IndonesiaKoordinat: 2°16′00″N 100°06′00″E / 2.26667°N 100.1°E / 2.26667; 100.1Ne...
село Адамівка Країна Україна Область Чернігівська область Район Ніжинський район Громада Носівська міська громада Код КАТОТТГ UA74040290020085155 Основні дані Засноване Середина 1630-х років [1] Населення 464 Площа 1,2 км² Густота населення 386,67 осіб/км² Поштовий індекс 17...
Geraldine Page c. 1950s Geraldine Page (November 22, 1924 – June 13, 1987) was an American actress who earned critical recognition as a stage actress on Broadway as well as in feature films and television. Over the course of her career, which spanned over three decades, Page earned a total of eight Academy Award nominations, three Emmy nominations, and four Tony nominations. She won the Academy Award for Best Actress for her performance in The Trip to Bountiful (1985). Screen F...
У этого термина существуют и другие значения, см. Не тронь меня. Не следует путать с «Не тронь меня» — плавучей зенитной батареей № 3 времён Великой Отечественной войны. Не тронь меня 1900-е, фотоателье Буллы Служба Российская империя Класс и тип судна Броненосная пла�...
Form of broadcast entertainment Lux Radio Theatre ad art featuring Joan Crawford An anthology series is a radio, television, film, or video game series that presents a different story and a different set of characters in each different episode, season, segment, or short.[1] These usually have a different cast in each episode, but several series in the past, such as Four Star Playhouse, employed a permanent troupe of character actors who would appear in a different drama each week.[...
1932 film The Famous Ferguson CaseTitular screenshotDirected byLloyd BaconWritten byHarvey F. ThewCourtney TerrettGranville MooreStarringJoan BlondellGrant MitchellVivienne OsborneCinematographyDevereaux JenningsEdited byHoward BrethertonMusic byBernhard KaunProductioncompanyFirst National PicturesDistributed byWarner Bros.Release dateMay 14, 1932Running time74 minutesCountryUnited StatesLanguageEnglish The Famous Ferguson Case is a 1932 American pre-Code crime film starring Joan Blondell and...
Indonesian footballer Tan See HanPersonal informationDate of birth 1910Place of birth Dutch East IndiesPosition(s) Forward (striker)Senior career*Years Team Apps (Gls) Tiong Hoa Soerabaja International career Dutch East Indies *Club domestic league appearances and goals This article relies largely or entirely on a single source. Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page. Please help improve this article by introducing citations to additional sources.Find sources: Tan See Han ...
Darwin Mobile ForceThe Darwin Mobile Force marches in battle order near the Vestey meatworks in April 1939Active1938–1940Country AustraliaBranchAustralian ArmySize245 men all ranksPart ofHQ 7th Military DistrictEngagementsSecond World WarMilitary unit The Darwin Mobile Force was a mixed force of infantry and artillery raised by the Australian Army prior to the Second World War.[1] It was the first regular infantry field force in the Australian military,[2] although due ...
This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: PZL.49 Miś – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (November 2008) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) PZL.49 Miś Possibly a side drawing from one of the few surviving pieces of documentation on this design. Role BomberType of aircraft ...
Ladybird BooksParent companyPenguin Random HouseFounded1867; 156 years ago (1867)Loughborough, Leicestershire, EnglandFounderHenry WillsCountry of originUnited KingdomHeadquarters locationLondonPublication typesBooksFiction genresChildrenOfficial websitewww.ladybird.co.uk Angel Yard, Loughborough. Ladybird Books green plaque, Angel Yard, Loughborough. Ladybird Books is a London-based publishing company, trading as a stand-alone imprint within the Penguin Group of companies. ...
Sroto Kriyik adalah hidangan soto khas Purbalingga, Jawa Tengah. Sroto kriyik (soto) memiliki ciri khas yaitu sroto yang berisi kuah yang rasanya khas disantap dalam keadaan panas, dan ditaburi daging ayam yang digoreng sangat garing. Selain itu kriyiknya juga ada dari tepung beras yang digoreng sangat garing, dan kerupuk. kriyik: kepala ayam, tepung beras yang digoreng garing, tulang bagian-bagian dari ayam yang juga digoreng garing, kerupuk. Biasanya telur pindang digunakan sebagai pelengka...
Place in Fashoda State, South SudanKodok CountyCountry South SudanStateFashoda State • Summer (DST)+3GMT Kodok County is an administrative area in Fashoda State, South Sudan. [1][2] References ^ The 32 Federal States of the Republic of South Sudan. paanluelwel.com. 29 December 2018. ^ The 32 States of the Republic of South Sudan. hotinjuba.com. 29 December 2018. This South Sudan-related article is a stub. You can help Wikipedia by expanding it.vte
For the historic building formerly occupied by this church, see Felton Presbyterian Church (historic building). Felton Presbyterian Church is a moderately sized church located in Felton, California. Church in CA , United StatesFelton Presbyterian ChurchFelton Presbyterian Church37°02′57″N 122°04′21″W / 37.049215°N 122.072603°W / 37.049215; -122.072603Location6050 Highway 9, Felton, CA 95018CountryUnited StatesDenominationECO: A Covenant Order of Evangelical...
For the city in Kern County formerly with this name, see McFarland, California. Census-designated place in California, United StatesLone PineCensus-designated placeMain StreetLocation in Inyo County and the state of CaliforniaLone PineLocation in the United StatesCoordinates: 36°36′22″N 118°03′46″W / 36.60611°N 118.06278°W / 36.60611; -118.06278Country United StatesState CaliforniaCountyInyoArea[1] • Total19.215 sq mi...