Verificationism

Verificationism, also known as the verification principle or the verifiability criterion of meaning, is a doctrine in philosophy which asserts that a statement is meaningful only if it is either empirically verifiable (can be confirmed through the senses) or a tautology (true by virtue of its own meaning or its own logical form). Verificationism rejects statements of metaphysics, theology, ethics and aesthetics as meaningless in conveying truth value or factual content, though they may be meaningful in influencing emotions or behavior.[1]

Verificationism was a central thesis of logical positivism, a movement in analytic philosophy that emerged in the 1920s by philosophers who sought to unify philosophy and science under a common naturalistic theory of knowledge.[2] The verifiability criterion underwent various revisions throughout the 1920s to 1950s. However, by the 1960s, it was deemed to be irreparably untenable.[3] Its abandonment would eventually precipitate the collapse of the broader logical positivist movement.[4]

Origins

The roots of verificationism may be traced to at least the 19th century, in philosophical principles that aim to ground scientific theory in verifiable experience, such as C.S. Peirce's pragmatism and the work of conventionalist Pierre Duhem,[3] who fostered instrumentalism.[5] Verificationism, as principle, would be conceived in the 1920s by the logical positivists of the Vienna Circle, who sought an epistemology whereby philosophical discourse would be, in their perception, as authoritative and meaningful as empirical science.[6] The movement established grounding in the empiricism of David Hume,[7] Auguste Comte and Ernst Mach, and the positivism of the latter two, borrowing perspectives from Immanuel Kant and defining their exemplar of science in Einstein's general theory of relativity.[8]

Ludwig Wittgenstein's Tractatus, published in 1921, established the theoretical foundations for the verifiability criterion of meaning.[9] Building upon Gottlob Frege's work, the analytic–synthetic distinction was also reformulated, reducing logic and mathematics to semantical conventions. This would render logical truths (being unverifiable by the senses) tenable under verificationism, as tautologies.[10]

Revisions

Logical positivists within the Vienna Circle recognized quickly that the verifiability criterion was too stringent. Specifically, universal generalizations were noted to be empirically unverifiable, rendering vital domains of science and reason, including scientific hypothesis, meaningless under verificationism, absent revisions to its criterion of meaning.[11]

Rudolf Carnap, Otto Neurath, Hans Hahn and Philipp Frank led a faction seeking to make the verifiability criterion more inclusive, beginning a movement they referred to as the "liberalization of empiricism". Moritz Schlick and Friedrich Waismann led a "conservative wing" that maintained a strict verificationism. Whereas Schlick sought to redefine universal generalizations as tautological rules, thereby to reconcile them with the existing criterion, Hahn argued that the criterion itself should be weakened to accommodate non-conclusive verification.[12] Neurath, within the liberal wing, proposed the adoption of coherentism, though challenged by Schlick's foundationalism. However, his physicalism would eventually be adopted over Mach's phenomenalism by most members of the Vienna Circle.[11][13]

In 1936, Carnap sought a switch from verification to confirmation.[11] Carnap's confirmability criterion (confirmationism) would not require conclusive verification (thus accommodating for universal generalizations) but allow for partial testability to establish degrees of confirmation on a probabilistic basis. Carnap never succeeded in finalising his thesis despite employing abundant logical and mathematical tools for this purpose. In all of Carnap's formulations, a universal law's degree of confirmation was zero.[14]

In Language, Truth and Logic, published that year, A. J. Ayer distinguished between strong and weak verification. This system espoused conclusive verification, yet allowed for probabilistic inclusion where verifiability is inconclusive. He also distinguished theoretical from practical verifiability, proposing that statements that are verifiable in principle should be meaningful, even if unverifiable in practice.[15][16]

Criticisms

Philosopher Karl Popper, a graduate of the University of Vienna, though not a member within the ranks of the Vienna Circle, was among the foremost critics of verificationism. He identified three fundamental deficiencies in verifiability as a criterion of meaning:[17]

  • Verificationism rejects universal generalizations, such as "all swans are white," as meaningless. Popper argues that while universal statements cannot be verified, they can be proven false, a foundation on which he was to propose his criterion of falsifiability.
  • Verificationism allows existential statements, such as “unicorns exist”, to be classified as scientifically meaningful, despite the absence of any definitive method to show that they are false (one could possibly find a unicorn somewhere not yet examined).
  • Verificationism is meaningless by virtue of its own criterion because it cannot be empirically verified. Thus the concept is self-defeating.

Popper regarded scientific hypotheses to never be completely verifiable, as well as not confirmable under Carnap's thesis.[9][18] He also considered metaphysical, ethical and aesthetic statements often rich in meaning and important in the origination of scientific theories.[9]

Other philosophers also voiced their own criticisms of verificationism:

Falsifiability

In The Logic of Scientific Discovery (1959), Popper proposed falsifiability, or falsificationism. Though formulated in the context of what he perceived were intractable problems in both verifiability and confirmability, Popper intended falsifiability, not as a criterion of meaning like verificationism (as commonly misunderstood),[24] but as a criterion to demarcate scientific statements from non-scientific statements.[9]

Notably, the falsifiability criterion would allow for scientific hypotheses (expressed as universal generalizations) to be held as provisionally true until proven false by observation, whereas under verificationism, they would be disqualified immediately as meaningless.[9]

In formulating his criterion, Popper was informed by the contrasting methodologies of Albert Einstein and Sigmund Freud. Appealing to the general theory of relativity and its predicted effects on gravitational lensing, it was evident to Popper that Einstein's theories carried significantly greater predictive risk than Freud's of being falsified by observation. Though Freud found ample confirmation of his theories in observations, Popper would note that this method of justification was vulnerable to confirmation bias, leading in some cases to contradictory outcomes. He would therefore conclude that predictive risk, or falsifiability, should serve as the criterion to demarcate the boundaries of science.[25]

Though falsificationism has been criticized extensively by philosophers for methodological shortcomings in its intended demarcation of science,[17] it would receive acclamatory adoption among scientists.[18] Logical positivists too adopted the criterion, even as their movement ran its course, catapulting Popper, initially a contentious misfit, to carry the richest philosophy out of interwar Vienna.[24]

Legacy

In 1967, John Passmore, a leading historian of 20th-century philosophy, wrote, "Logical positivism is dead, or as dead as a philosophical movement ever becomes".[4] Logical positivism's fall heralded postpositivism, where Popper's view of human knowledge as hypothetical, continually growing and open to change ascended[24] and verificationism, in academic circles, became mostly maligned.[3]

In a 1976 TV interview, A. J. Ayer, who had introduced logical positivism to the English-speaking world in the 1930s[26] was asked what he saw as its main defects, and answered that "nearly all of it was false".[4] However, he soon said that he still held "the same general approach", referring to empiricism and reductionism, whereby mental phenomena resolve to the material or physical and philosophical questions largely resolve to ones of language and meaning.[4] In 1977, Ayer had noted:[3]

"The verification principle is seldom mentioned and when it is mentioned it is usually scorned; it continues, however, to be put to work. The attitude of many philosophers reminds me of the relationship between Pip and Magwitch in Dickens's Great Expectations. They have lived on the money, but are ashamed to acknowledge its source."

In 1946 R.B. Braithwaite stated that "those of us who are not convinced by the anti-metaphysical thesis of the logical positivists have not been unscathed by it. Few philosophers nowadays speak of Absolute Reality or the Absolute Mind in the familiar way in which it was discussed by metaphysicians at the end of the last century".[27]

In the late 20th and early 21st centuries, the general concept of verification criteria—in forms that differed from those of the logical positivists—was defended by Bas van Fraassen, Michael Dummett, Crispin Wright, Christopher Peacocke, David Wiggins, Richard Rorty, and others.[3]

See also

References

  1. ^ "Verifiability principle". Encyclopædia Britannica. 2024. Retrieved 8 October 2024.
  2. ^ Uebel, Thomas (2024). "Vienna Circle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 October 2024.
  3. ^ a b c d e Misak, C.J. (1995). "The Logical Positivists and the Verifiability Principle". Verificationism: Its History and Prospects. New York: Routledge.
  4. ^ a b c d Hanfling, Oswald (1996). "Logical positivism". In Stuart G Shanker (ed.). Philosophy of Science, Logic and Mathematics in the Twentieth Century. Routledge. pp. 193–94.
  5. ^ Epstein, Miran (2012). "Introduction to philosophy of science". In Clive Seale (ed.). Researching Society and Culture 3rd Ed. London: Sage Publications. pp. 18–19.
  6. ^ Uebel 2024 Section 2.2
  7. ^ Flew, Antony G (1984). "Science: Conjectures and refutations". In Andrew Bailey (ed.). A Dictionary of Philosophy. New York: St Martin's Press. p. 156. Despite Hume's radical empiricism, set forth near 1740, Hume was also committed to common sense and apparently did not take his own skepticism, such as the problem of induction, as drastically as others later did.
  8. ^ Uebel 2024 Section 3
  9. ^ a b c d e Popper, Karl (2011). "Science: Conjectures and refutations". In Andrew Bailey (ed.). First Philosophy: Fundamental Problems and Readings in Philosophy (2 ed.). Peterborough Ontario: Broadview Press. pp. 338–42.
  10. ^ Jerrold J. Katz (2000). "The epistemic challenge to antirealism". Realistic Rationalism. MIT Press. p. 69. ISBN 978-0262263290.
  11. ^ a b c Sahotra Sarkar; Jessica Pfeifer, eds. (2006). "Rudolf Carnap". The Philosophy of Science: An Encyclopedia, Volume 1: A-M. New York: Routledge. p. 83.
  12. ^ Uebel 2024 Section 3.1
  13. ^ Flew 1984 p.245
  14. ^ Murzi, Mauro (2001). "Rudolf Carnap (1891–1970)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  15. ^ Ayer, A.J. (1936). Language, Truth, and Logic (PDF). pp. 6–7.
  16. ^ Ayer, A.J. (29 November 2007). "Ayer on the criterion of verifiability" (PDF). Retrieved 9 July 2023.
  17. ^ a b Shea, Brendan. "Karl Popper: Philosophy of Science". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved May 12, 2019.
  18. ^ a b Godfrey-Smith, Peter (2005). Theory and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 57–59.
  19. ^ Rocknak, Stefanie. "Willard Van Orman Quine: The Analytic/Synthetic Distinction". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved July 14, 2024.
  20. ^ Fetzer, James (2013). "Carl Hempel". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 8 October 2024.
  21. ^ Caldwell, Bruce (1994). Beyond Positivism: Economic Methodology in the 20th Century. London: Routledge. pp. 47–48.
  22. ^ Okasha, Samir (2002). "Scientific Change and Scientific Revolutions". Philosophy of Science: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  23. ^ Uebel 2024 Section 3.3
  24. ^ a b c Hacohen, Malachi Haim (2000). Karl Popper: The Formative Years, 1902–1945: Politics and Philosophy in Interwar Vienna. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 212–13.
  25. ^ Popper, Karl (1962). Conjectures and Refutations: The Growth of Scientific Knowledge (2 ed.). Routledge. pp. 34–37.
  26. ^ Chapman, Siobhan (2009). "Logical positivism". In Siobhan Chapman; Christopher Routledge (eds.). Key ideas in linguistics and the philosophy of language. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
  27. ^ Braithwaite, R.B. (1946). "The Inaugural Address: Belief and Action". Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volumes. 20: 1–19.

Read other articles:

Iluminasi yang menggambarkan pertobatan Paulus, dari Livre d'Heures d'Étienne Chevalier (c. 1450–1460), sebuah buku ibadat harian karya Jean Fouquet yang sekarang berada di Château de Chantilly.  Bagian dari seriAlkitab Kanon Alkitabdan kitab-kitabnya Tanak(Taurat · Nevi'im · Ketuvim)Kanon Alkitab Kristen · Alkitab IbraniPerjanjian Lama (PL) · Perjanjian Baru (PB) Deuterokanonika · Antilegomena Bab dan ayat dalam Alkitab Apokrifa...

 

يفتقر محتوى هذه المقالة إلى الاستشهاد بمصادر. فضلاً، ساهم في تطوير هذه المقالة من خلال إضافة مصادر موثوق بها. أي معلومات غير موثقة يمكن التشكيك بها وإزالتها. (أكتوبر 2019) تويوتا بليزاردمعلومات عامةالنوع سيارة طرق وعرة العلامة التجارية تويوتا المصنع دايهاتسوالإنتاج 1980-1990ال...

 

Torajirō SaitōLokasi syuting film Koisuredo Koisuredo Monogatari (1956). Tokoh di depan dari kanan ke kiri, Sutradara Torajiro Saito, Tony Tani, Ichiro Arishima, dan Mariko Miyagi.Lahir(1905-01-30)30 Januari 1905.Distrik Yuri Prefektur AkitaMeninggal1 Mei 1982(1982-05-01) (umur 77)KebangsaanJepangNama lainDewa KomediPekerjaanSutradara filmTahun aktif1926-1962Dikenal atasMenyutradarai lebih dari 200 film slapstick dan komedi omong kosongKarya terkenalKodakara SodoSuami/istriTo...

يو-657 الجنسية  ألمانيا النازية الشركة الصانعة ها دي ڤيه  المالك  كريغسمارينه المشغل كريغسمارينه[1][2]  المشغلون الحاليون وسيط property غير متوفر. المشغلون السابقون وسيط property غير متوفر. التكلفة وسيط property غير متوفر. منظومة التعاريف الاَلية للسفينة وسيط property غير ...

 

Dit artikel geeft een overzicht van de geschiedenis van Nijmegen. Oudste sporen Nijmegen is naast Maastricht, Voorburg en Heerlen een van de vier steden die de titel oudste stad van Nederland claimen. In het jaar 2005 werd het 2000-jarig bestaan van de stad en het 1900-jarig bezit van stadsrechten gevierd. Sporen van bewoning zijn al bekend uit het Neolithicum, de midden en late bronstijd en (ten noorden van de Waal) uit de midden en late ijzertijd. Romeinen Schematische weergave van Oppidum ...

 

У этого топонима есть и другие значения, см. Горка. ДеревняГорка 57°57′45″ с. ш. 35°35′05″ в. д.HGЯO Страна  Россия Субъект Федерации Тверская область Муниципальный район Максатихинский Сельское поселение Малышевское История и география Часовой пояс UTC+3:00 Населен...

هذه المقالة تحتاج للمزيد من الوصلات للمقالات الأخرى للمساعدة في ترابط مقالات الموسوعة. فضلًا ساعد في تحسين هذه المقالة بإضافة وصلات إلى المقالات المتعلقة بها الموجودة في النص الحالي. (أبريل 2023) قالب:صندوق معلومات صيني我的父亲。 习近平:我又病又累,在重症监护室,手里有营养品免水,我们...

 

Overview of the role and impact of Hinduism in the Pakistani province of Punjab Punjabi Hindus of PakistanHindus in Cholistan celebrating HoliTotal population211,641 (2017) 0.2% of total Province populationReligionsHinduism (majority)Nanakpanthi and KalashScripturesBhagavad Gita, and VedasGuru Granth Sahib (only by Nanakpanthi)LanguagesSanskrit (sacred)Punjabi, Marwari, Saraiki[1]Hindi, Urdu and other languages (minority) Hinduism is a minority religion in Punjab province of Pakistan ...

 

Чемпионат мира по сноуборду 2012 года — 1-й в истории чемпионат мира, придуманный и созданный Ticket to Ride (TTR) совместно со Всемирной федерацией сноуборда (WSF). Прошел с 10 по 19 февраля 2012 года в столице Норвегии, Осло. В дисциплинах слоупстайл и хафпайп за звание чемпиона мира п...

2015 studio album by of MontrealAureate GloomStudio album by of MontrealReleasedMarch 2, 2015RecordedSonic Ranch (Tornillo, Texas)GenreGlam rock[1][2]Length43:28LabelPolyvinylProducerKevin BarnesOf Montreal chronology Lousy with Sylvianbriar(2013) Aureate Gloom(2015) Innocence Reaches(2016) Singles from Aureate Gloom Bassem SabryReleased: December 9, 2014 Aureate Gloom is the thirteenth studio album by indie rock band of Montreal. It was released in the UK on March 2, ...

 

العلاقات الأندورية الغيانية أندورا غيانا   أندورا   غيانا تعديل مصدري - تعديل   العلاقات الأندورية الغيانية هي العلاقات الثنائية التي تجمع بين أندورا وغيانا.[1][2][3][4][5] مقارنة بين البلدين هذه مقارنة عامة ومرجعية للدولتين: وجه المقارنة أندور...

 

1991 single by Ian McNabbGreat Dreams of HeavenSingle by Ian McNabbfrom the album Truth and Beauty ReleasedJuly 1991, March 1993GenreRockLabelWay Cool Records/This Way UpSongwriter(s)Robert Ian McNabbProducer(s)Robert Ian McNabbIan McNabb singles chronology Great Dreams of Heaven (1991) These Are the Days (1991) Great Dreams of Heaven is the first solo single released by Ian McNabb after disbanding the Icicle Works. It was first released in 1991, then re-released in 1993 from the album Truth ...

This article may have been created or edited in return for undisclosed payments, a violation of Wikipedia's terms of use. It may require cleanup to comply with Wikipedia's content policies, particularly neutral point of view. (March 2020) Dutch Wheels (Vekoma) R50 transportable Ferris wheel in Delhi, IndiaAtlantic Water WorldGeneral informationTypeDutch Wheels (Vekoma) R50 transportable Ferris wheel[1][2]LocationDelhi, IndiaCompleted2010[1]Opened2014[1]CostAppr...

 

Myles Mack Mack en St. Anthony HSDatos personalesNacimiento Paterson, Nueva Jersey Estados Unidos25 de febrero de 1993 (30 años)Nacionalidad(es) EstadounidenseAltura 1,78 m (5′ 10″)Peso 79 kg (174 lb)Carrera deportivaDeporte BaloncestoEquipo universitario Rutgers (2011-2015)Club profesionalDraft de la NBA No elegido, 2015Club MKE AnkaragücüLiga TBLPosición BaseDorsal(es) 2Trayectoria KK Alytaus Dzūkija (2015) Horsens IC (2016-2017) Turów Zgorzelec (2017) GTK Gliw...

 

كاس الغارفى 2019 البلد پورتوجال  الرياضه كورة قدم  الموسم 26  تاريخ 2019  تاريخ الانتهاء 6 مارس 2019  عدد المشاركين عدد المباريات تعديل  كاس الغارفى 2019 (بالانجليزى: 2019 Algarve Cup) هوا موسم رياضى فى كورة قدم اتعمل فى پورتوجال سنة 2019. معلومات الموسم كاس الغارفى 2019 هوا الموسم...

Defunct American women's basketball league Bikini Basketball AssociationMost recent season or competition:2014 Bikini Basketball Association seasonSportBasketballFounded2012; 11 years ago (2012)Inaugural season2013CEOA. J. McArthurMottoIn a League of its OwnNo. of teams3Country United StatesMost recentchampion(s)Illinois HeartMost titlesIllinois Heart (2 titles)Official websitebikinibasketball.com The Bikini Basketball Association (BBA) was an American women's basketbal...

 

It has been suggested that this article be merged with Cannabis. (Discuss) Proposed since November 2023. Species of plant This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Cannabis ruderalis – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (December 2018) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) Canna...

 

Brazilian TV series or program JesusPromotional posterGenre Telenovela Drama Epic Created byPaula RichardWritten by Joaquim de Assis Larissa de Oliveira Méuri Luiza Natália Piserni Natália Sambrini Rodrigo Ribeiro Directed byEdgard MirandaStarring Dudu Azevedo Opening themePreciosoby Marcello BraynerCountry of originBrazilOriginal languagePortugueseNo. of seasons1No. of episodes193ProductionCamera setupMulti-cameraProduction companies RecordTV Casablanca Original releaseNetworkRecordT...

矢印の角度が赤道傾斜角(左から地球、天王星、金星の順) 赤道傾斜角(せきどうけいしゃかく、英語: axial tilt、obliquity)とは、惑星や衛星など、自転(あくまでも天体は地球のように西から東へ自転するのが通常と仮定した場合)しつつ公転運動する天体の軌道面と赤道面のなす角である。自転軸と公転軸のなす角に等しいため、自転軸傾斜角とも言う。この角は...

 

1977 NCAA Division I Swimming and Diving ChampionshipsHost city Cleveland, OhioDate(s)March 1977Venue(s)CSU NatatoriumCleveland State University← 1976 1978 → The 1977 NCAA Men's Division I Swimming and Diving Championships were contested in March 1977 at the Cleveland State University Natatorium at Cleveland State University in Cleveland, Ohio at the 54th annual NCAA-sanctioned swim meet to determine the team and individual national champions of Division I men's collegiate swimmin...

 

Strategi Solo vs Squad di Free Fire: Cara Menang Mudah!