From 1963 to 1982, Plantinga taught at Calvin University before accepting an appointment as the John A. O'Brien Professor of Philosophy at the University of Notre Dame.[2] He later returned to Calvin University to become the inaugural holder of the Jellema Chair in Philosophy.[3]
A prominent Christian philosopher, Plantinga served as president of the Society of Christian Philosophers from 1983 to 1986. He has delivered the Gifford Lectures twice and was described by Time magazine as "America's leading orthodox Protestant philosopher of God".[4] In 2014, Plantinga was the 30th most-cited contemporary author in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.[5] A fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences, he was awarded the Templeton Prize in 2017.
Some of Plantinga's most influential works include God and Other Minds (1967), The Nature of Necessity (1974), and a trilogy of books on epistemology, culminating in Warranted Christian Belief (2000) that was simplified in Knowledge and Christian Belief (2015).[6]
Biography
Family
Plantinga was born on November 15, 1932, in Ann Arbor, Michigan, to Cornelius A. Plantinga (1908–1994) and Lettie G. Bossenbroek (1908–2007), immigrants from the province of Friesland in the Netherlands.[7] After Cornelius earned a PhD in philosophy from Duke University, he secured a teaching job in Michigan in 1941.[8] Cornelius also had a master's degree in psychology. He taught several academic subjects at different institutions throughout his career.[9]
As an adolescent, Alvin Plantinga's family moved from Michigan to North Dakota for his father's job at Jamestown College. At his father's advice, Alvin skipped his last year of high school to enroll at Jamestown College in 1949 at 16.[14][15] That year, his father accepted a teaching job at Calvin University which began in January 1950. Alvin Plantinga moved to Grand Rapids with his family and attended Calvin University for a semester. He applied to Harvard and was awarded a scholarship.[16]
In the fall of 1950, Plantinga transferred to Harvard, where he spent two semesters. In 1951, during Harvard's spring recess, Plantinga attended a few philosophy classes at Calvin University and was so impressed with Calvin philosophy professor William Harry Jellema that he returned in 1951 to study philosophy under him.[17] In 1954, Plantinga began his graduate studies at the University of Michigan where he studied under William Alston, William Frankena, and Richard Cartwright, among others.[18] A year later, in 1955, he transferred to Yale University where he received his PhD in 1958.[19]
Teaching career
Plantinga began his career as an instructor in the philosophy department at Yale in 1957, and then in 1958, he became a professor of philosophy at Wayne State University during its heyday as a major center for analytic philosophy. In 1963, he accepted a teaching job at Calvin University, where he replaced the retiring Jellema.[20] He then spent the next 19 years at Calvin before moving to the University of Notre Dame in 1982. He retired from the University of Notre Dame in 2010 and returned to Calvin University, where he holds the first William Harry Jellema Chair in Philosophy. He has trained metaphysics and epistemology-focused philosophers including Michael Bergmann, Michael Rea, and Trenton Merricks.
In 2006, the University of Notre Dame's Center for Philosophy of Religion renamed its Distinguished Scholar Fellowship as the Alvin Plantinga Fellowship.[23] The fellowship includes an annual lecture by the current Plantinga Fellow.[24]
In 2012, the University of Pittsburgh's Philosophy Department, History and Philosophy of Science Department, and the Center for the History and Philosophy of Science co-awarded Plantinga the Nicholas Rescher Prize for Systematic Philosophy,[25] which he received with a talk titled, "Religion and Science: Where the Conflict Really Lies".
In 2017, Baylor University's Center for Christian Philosophy inaugurated the Alvin Plantinga Award for Excellence in Christian Philosophy. Awardees deliver a lecture at Baylor University and their name is put on a plaque with Plantinga's image in the Institute for Studies in Religion. He was named the first fellow of the center as well.[26]
Plantinga has argued that some people can know that God exists as a basic belief, requiring no argument. He developed this argument in two different ways: firstly, in God and Other Minds (1967), by drawing an equivalence between the teleological argument and the common sense view that people have of other minds existing by analogy with their own minds.[28][29] Plantinga has also developed a more comprehensive epistemological account of the nature of warrant which allows for the existence of God as a basic belief.[30]
Plantinga has also argued that there is no logical inconsistency between the existence of evil and the existence of an all-powerful, all-knowing, wholly good God.[31]
Plantinga proposed a "free-will defense" in a volume edited by Max Black in 1965,[32] which attempts to refute the logical problem of evil, the argument that the existence of evil is logically incompatible with the existence of an omnipotent, omniscient, wholly good God.[33] Plantinga's argument (in a truncated form) states that "It is possible that God, even being omnipotent, could not create a world with free creatures who never choose evil. Furthermore, it is possible that God, even being omnibenevolent, would desire to create a world which contains evil if moral goodness requires free moral creatures."[34]
However, the argument's handling of natural evil has been disputed. According to the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, the argument also "conflicts with important theistic doctrines" such as the notion of a heaven where free saved souls reside without doing evil, and the idea that God has free will yet is wholly good. Critics thus maintain that, if we take such doctrines to be (as Christians usually have), God could have created free creatures that always do right, contra Plantinga's claim.[35]J. L. Mackie saw Plantinga's free-will defense as incoherent.[36]
Plantinga's well-received book God, Freedom and Evil, written in 1974, gave his response to what he saw as the incomplete and uncritical view of theism's criticism of theodicy. Plantinga's contribution stated that when the issue of a comprehensive doctrine of freedom is added to the discussion of the goodness of God and the omnipotence of God then it is not possible to exclude the presence of evil in the world after introducing freedom into the discussion. Plantinga's own summary occurs in his discussion titled "Could God Have Created a World Containing Moral Good but No Moral Evil", where he states his conclusion that, "... the price for creating a world in which they produce moral good is creating one in which they also produce moral evil."[37]
What Plantinga calls "Reformed epistemology" holds that belief in God can be rational and justified even without arguments or evidence for the existence of God. More specifically, he argues belief in God is properly basic, and due to a religious externalist epistemology, he claims that it could be justified independently of evidence. His externalist epistemology, called "proper functionalism", is a form of epistemologicalreliabilism.
Plantinga discusses his view of Reformed epistemology and proper functionalism in a three-volume series. In the first book of the trilogy, Warrant: The Current Debate, Plantinga introduces, analyzes, and criticizes 20th-century developments in analytic epistemology, particularly the works of Chisholm, BonJour, Alston, Goldman, and others.[38] In the book, Plantinga argues specifically that the theories of what he calls "warrant"—what many others have called justification (Plantinga draws out a difference: justification is a property of a person holding a belief while warrant is a property of a belief)—put forth by these epistemologists have systematically failed to capture in full what is required for knowledge.[39]
In the second book, Warrant and Proper Function, he introduces the notion of warrant as an alternative to justification and discusses topics like self-knowledge, memories, perception, and probability.[40] Plantinga's "proper function" account argues that as a necessary condition of having warrant, one's "belief-forming and belief-maintaining apparatus of powers" are functioning properly—"working the way it ought to work".[41] Plantinga explains his argument for proper function with reference to a "design plan", as well as an environment in which one's cognitive equipment is optimal for use. Plantinga asserts that the design plan does not require a designer: "it is perhaps possible that evolution (undirected by God or anyone else) has somehow furnished us with our design plans",[42] but the paradigm case of a design plan is like a technological product designed by a human being (like a radio or a wheel). Ultimately, Plantinga argues that epistemological naturalism- i.e. epistemology that holds that warrant is dependent on natural faculties—is best supported by supernaturalist metaphysics—in this case, the belief in a creator God or designer who has laid out a design plan that includes cognitive faculties conducive to attaining knowledge.[43]
According to Plantinga, a belief, B, is warranted if:
(1) the cognitive faculties involved in the production of B are functioning properly…; (2) your cognitive environment is sufficiently similar to the one for which your cognitive faculties are designed; (3) … the design plan governing the production of the belief in question involves, as purpose or function, the production of true beliefs…; and (4) the design plan is a good one: that is, there is a high statistical or objective probability that a belief produced in accordance with the relevant segment of the design plan in that sort of environment is true.[44]
Plantinga seeks to defend this view of proper function against alternative views of proper function proposed by other philosophers which he groups together as "naturalistic", including the "functional generalization" view of John Pollock, the evolutionary/etiological account provided by Ruth Millikan, and a dispositional view held by John Bigelow and Robert Pargetter.[45] Plantinga also discusses his evolutionary argument against naturalism in the later chapters of Warrant and Proper Function.[46]
In 2000, the third book of the trilogy, Warranted Christian Belief, was published. In this volume, Plantinga's warrant theory is the basis for his theological end: providing a philosophical basis for Christian belief, an argument for why Christian theistic belief can enjoy warrant. In the book, he develops two models for such beliefs, the "A/C" (Aquinas/Calvin) model, and the "Extended A/C" model. The former attempts to show that a belief in God can be justified, warranted and rational, while the Extended model tries to show that specifically Christian theological beliefs including the Trinity, the Incarnation, the resurrection of Christ, the atonement, salvation. etc. Under this model, Christians are justified in their beliefs because of the work of the Holy Spirit in bringing those beliefs about in the believer.
James Beilby has argued that the purpose of Plantinga's Warrant trilogy, and specifically of his Warranted Christian Belief, is firstly to make a form of argument against religion impossible—namely, the argument that whether or not Christianity is true, it is irrational—so "the skeptic would have to shoulder the formidable task of demonstrating the falsity of Christian belief"[47] rather than simply dismiss it as irrational. In addition, Plantinga is attempting to provide a philosophical explanation of how Christians should think about their own Christian belief.
Plantinga criticized Malcolm's and Hartshorne's arguments, and offered an alternative.[48] He argued that, if Malcolm does prove the necessary existence of the greatest possible being, it follows that there is a being which exists in all worlds whose greatness in some worlds is not surpassed. It does not, he argued, demonstrate that such a being has unsurpassed greatness in this world.[49]
In an attempt to resolve this problem, Plantinga differentiated between "greatness" and "excellence". A being's excellence in a particular world depends only on its properties in that world; a being's greatness depends on its properties in all worlds. Therefore, the greatest possible being must have maximal excellence in every possible world. Plantinga then restated Malcolm's argument, using the concept of "maximal greatness". He argued that it is possible for a being with maximal greatness to exist, so a being with maximal greatness exists in a possible world. If this is the case, then a being with maximal greatness exists in every world, and therefore in this world.[49]
The conclusion relies on a form of modal axiom S5, which states that if something is possibly true, then its possibility is necessary (it is possibly true in all worlds). Plantinga's version of S5 suggests that "To say that p is possibly necessarily true is to say that, with regard to one world, it is true at all worlds; but in that case it is true at all worlds, and so it is simply necessary."[50] A version of his argument is as follows:[51]
A being has maximal excellence in a given possible world W if and only if it is omnipotent, omniscient and wholly good in W; and
A being has maximal greatness if it has maximal excellence in every possible world.
It is possible that there is a being that has maximal greatness. (Premise)
Therefore, possibly, it is necessarily true that an omniscient, omnipotent, and perfectly good being exists.
Therefore, (by axiom S5) it is necessarily true that an omniscient, omnipotent and perfectly good being exists.
Therefore, an omniscient, omnipotent and perfectly good being exists.
Plantinga argued that, although the first premise is not rationally established, it is not contrary to reason. Michael Martin argued that, if certain components of perfection are contradictory, such as omnipotence and omniscience, then the first premise is contrary to reason. Martin also proposed parodies of the argument, suggesting that the existence of anything can be demonstrated with Plantinga's argument, provided it is defined as perfect or special in every possible world.[52]
Another Christian philosopher, William Lane Craig, characterizes Plantinga's argument in a slightly different way:
It is possible that a maximally great being exists.
If it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then a maximally great being exists in some possible world.
If a maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
If a maximally great being exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world.
If a maximally great being exists in the actual world, then a maximally great being exists.
Therefore, a maximally great being exists.
According to Craig, premises (2)–(5) are relatively uncontroversial among philosophers, but "the epistemic entertainability of premise (1) (or its denial) does not guarantee its metaphysical possibility."[53] Furthermore, Richard M. Gale argued that premise three, the "possibility premise", begs the question. He stated that one only has the epistemic right to accept the premise if one understands the nested modal operators, and that if one understands them within the system S5—without which the argument fails—then one understands that "possibly necessarily" is in essence the same as "necessarily".[54] Thus the premise begs the question because the conclusion is embedded within it.
On S5 systems in general, James Garson writes that "the words 'necessarily' and 'possibly', have many different uses. So the acceptability of axioms for modal logic depends on which of these uses we have in mind."[55]
In Plantinga's evolutionary argument against naturalism, he argues that if evolution is true, it undermines naturalism. His basic argument is that if evolution and naturalism are both true, human cognitive faculties evolved to produce beliefs that have survival value (maximizing one's success at the four Fs: "feeding, fleeing, fighting, and reproducing"), not necessarily to produce beliefs that are true. Thus, since human cognitive faculties are tuned to survival rather than truth in the naturalism-evolution model, there is reason to doubt the veracity of the products of those same faculties, including naturalism and evolution themselves. On the other hand, if God created man "in his image" by way of an evolutionary process (or any other means), then Plantinga argues our faculties would probably be reliable.
The argument does not assume any necessary correlation (or uncorrelation) between true beliefs and survival. Making the contrary assumption—that there is, in fact, a relatively strong correlation between truth and survival—if human belief-forming apparatus evolved giving a survival advantage, then it ought to yield truth since true beliefs confer a survival advantage. Plantinga counters that, while there may be overlap between true beliefs and beliefs that contribute to survival, the two kinds of beliefs are not the same, and he gives the following example with a man named Paul:
Perhaps Paul very much likes the idea of being eaten, but when he sees a tiger, always runs off looking for a better prospect, because he thinks it unlikely the tiger he sees will eat him. This will get his body parts in the right place so far as survival is concerned, without involving much by way of true belief... Or perhaps he thinks the tiger is a large, friendly, cuddly pussycat and wants to pet it; but he also believes that the best way to pet it is to run away from it... Clearly there are any number of belief-desire systems that equally fit a given bit of behaviour.[56]
Even though Plantinga believes that God could have used Darwinian processes to create the world, he stands firm against philosophical naturalism. He said in an interview on the relationship between science and religion that:
Religion and science share more common ground than you might think, though science can't prove, it presupposes that there has been a past for example, science does not cover the whole of the knowledge enterprise.[61]
Plantinga participated in groups that support the Intelligent Design Movement, and was a member of the "Ad Hoc Origins Committee"[62] that supported Philip E. Johnson's 1991 book Darwin on Trial, he also provided a back-cover endorsement of Johnson's book: "Shows how Darwinian evolution has become an idol."[63]
Like any Christian (and indeed any theist), I believe that the world has been created by God, and hence "intelligently designed". The hallmark of intelligent design, however, is the claim that this can be shown scientifically; I'm dubious about that.
...As far as I can see, God certainly could have used Darwinian processes to create the living world and direct it as he wanted to go; hence evolution as such does not imply that there is no direction in the history of life. What does have that implication is not evolutionary theory itself, but unguided evolution, the idea that neither God nor any other person has taken a hand in guiding, directing or orchestrating the course of evolution. But the scientific theory of evolution, sensibly enough, says nothing one way or the other about divine guidance. It doesn't say that evolution is divinely guided; it also doesn't say that it isn't. Like almost any theist, I reject unguided evolution; but the contemporary scientific theory of evolution just as such—apart from philosophical or theological add-ons—doesn't say that evolution is unguided. Like science in general, it makes no pronouncements on the existence or activity of God.[67]
The attitude that he proposes and elaborates upon in Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion and Naturalism is that there is no tension between religion and science, that the two go hand in hand, and that the actual conflict lies between naturalism and science.[68]
^Felder, D. W. (1971). "Disanalogies in Plantinga's Argument regarding the Rationality of Theism". Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion. 10 (3): 200–207. doi:10.2307/1384479. JSTOR1384479.
^J. L. Mackie wrote: "[H]ow could there be logically contingent states of affairs, prior to the creation and existence of any created beings with free will, which an omnipotent god would have to accept and put up with? This suggestion is simply incoherent. Indeed, by bringing in the notion of individual essences which determine—presumably non-causally—how Curly Smith, Satan, and the rest of us would choose freely or would act in each hypothetical situation, Plantinga has not rescued the free will defence but made its weaknesses all too clear". Mackie 1982, p. 174.
^Plantinga, Alvin (1974). God, Freedom and Evil, p. 49.
^Alvin Plantinga, Warrant: The Current Debate, New York: Oxford University Press, 1993.
^Fales, E. (1996). "Plantinga's Case against Naturalistic Epistemology". Philosophy of Science. 63 (3): 432–451. doi:10.1086/289920. S2CID170510977.
^Beilby, James (2007). "Plantinga's Model of Warranted Christian Belief". In Baker, Deane-Peter (ed.). Alvin Plantinga. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 125–165. ISBN978-0-521-67143-9.
^ abPlantinga, Alvin (1998). Sennett, James F. (ed.). The Analytic Theist: An Alvin Plantinga Reader. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. pp. 65–71. ISBN978-0-8028-4229-9.
^Oppy, Graham (8 February 1996). "Ontological Arguments". substantive revision 15 July 2011. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
^Martin, Michael (2003). Philosophy of religion: an anthology. Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 282–293. ISBN978-0-631-21471-7.
^Craig, William Lane (2008). Reasonable faith. Crossway. p. 185. ISBN978-1-4335-0115-9. Premises (2)–(5) of this argument are relatively uncontroversial. Most philosophers would agree that if God's existence is even possible, then he must exist. ... the epistemic entertainability of premise (1) (or its denial) does not guarantee its metaphysical possibility.
^Gale, Richard (1993). On the Nature and Existence of God. Cambridge University Press. p. 227. ISBN0-521-45723-8.
^Garson, James (February 29, 2000). Modal Logic. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via plato.stanford.edu.
^Plantinga, Alvin Warrant and Proper Function, (New York: Oxford University Press), 1993. pp. 225–226 (ISBN978-0-19-507864-0).
^"Notre Dame philosopher Alvin Plantinga has also signed this letter" – We're Not in Kansas Anymore, Nancy Pearcey, Christianity Today, May 22, 2000, cited in Forrest & Gross 2004, p. 18 "Alvin Plantinga was also a signatory to this letter, early evidence of his continuing support of the intelligent design movement" – Intelligent design creationism and its critics, Robert T. Pennock (ed), 2001, p44
Schönecker, Dieter (ed.), Essays on "Warranted Christian Belief". With Replies by Alvin Plantinga. Walter de Gruyter, Berlin 2015.
Baker, Deane-Peter (ed), Alvin Plantinga (Contemporary Philosophy in Focus Series). New York: Cambridge University Press. 2007.
Mascrod, Keith, Alvin Plantinga and Christian Apologetics. Wipf & Stock. 2007.
Crisp, Thomas, Matthew Davidson, David Vander Laan (eds), Knowledge and Reality: Essays in Honor of Alvin Plantinga. Dordrecht: Springer. 2006.
Beilby, James, Epistemology as Theology: An Evaluation of Alvin Plantinga's Religious Epistemology. Aldershot: Ashgate. 2005
Beilby, James (ed), Naturalism Defeated? Essays on Plantinga's Evolutionary Argument Against Naturalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 2002.
Sennet, James (ed), The Analytic Theist: An Alvin Plantinga Reader. Grand Rapids: Eeardman. 1998. ISBN0-8028-4229-1
Kvanvig, Jonathan (ed), Warrant in Contemporary Epistemology: Essays in Honor of Plantinga's Theory of Knowledge. Savage, Maryland: Rowman & Littlefield. 1996.
McLeod, Mark S. Rationality and Theistic Belief: An Essay on Reformed Epistemology (Cornell Studies in the Philosophy of Religion). Ithaca: Cornell University Press. 1993.
Zagzebski, Linda (ed), Rational Faith. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. 1993.
Sennett, James, Modality, Probability, and Rationality: A Critical Examination of Alvin Plantinga's Philosophy. New York: P. Lang. 1992.
Hoitenga, Dewey, From Plato to Plantinga: An Introduction to Reformed Epistemology. Albany: State University of New York Press. 1991.
Parsons, Keith, God and the Burden of Proof: Plantinga, Swinburne, and the Analytic Defense of Theism. Buffalo, New York: Prometheus Books. 1989.
Tomberlin, James and Peter van Inwagen (eds), Alvin Plantinga (Profiles V.5). Dordrecht: D. Reidel. 1985.
Catur Budi HartoCatur Budi Harto sebagai Wakil Direktur Utama Bank Rakyat Indonesia (2019)Wakil Direktur Utama Bank Rakyat IndonesiaMasa jabatan2 September 2019 – sekarangPresidenJoko WidodoWakil PresidenMa'ruf AminDirektur Bidang Kredit Kecil & Menengah dan Jaringan Bank Negara IndonesiaMasa jabatan2017–2019PresidenJoko WidodoWakil PresidenJusuf Kalla Ma'ruf AminDirektur Bidang Jaringan dan Commercial Funding Layanan Bank Tabungan NegaraMasa jabatan2016–2017PresidenJoko Wi...
Overview of road signs in Hong Kong Road signs near Aberdeen Tunnel of Hong Kong Road signs in Hong Kong are standardised by the Transport Department.[1] Due to being a former British territory, the road signage in Hong Kong is similar to road signs in the United Kingdom, with the addition of Traditional Chinese characters. Design and language Latest road signs with Transport typeface (2015) Road signs in Hong Kong closely follow those used in the United Kingdom, and complies with the...
Bagian dari seriPendidikan di Indonesia Kementerian Pendidikan, Kebudayaan, Riset, dan Teknologi Republik Indonesia Pendidikan anak usia dini TK RA KB Pendidikan dasar (kelas 1–6) SD MI Paket A Pendidikan dasar (kelas 7–9) SMP MTs Paket B Pendidikan menengah (kelas 10–12) SMA MA SMK MAK SMA SMTK SMAK Utama Widya Pasraman Paket C Pendidikan tinggi Perguruan tinggi Akademi Akademi komunitas Institut Politeknik Sekolah tinggi Universitas Lain-lain Madrasah Pesantren Sekolah alam Sekolah ru...
Secretaría de Estado en los Despachos de Cultura, Artes y DeportesCoat of arms of HondurasSecretary of State overviewFormedJune 23, 1975 (1975-06-23)Preceding Secretary of StateSecretary of State for Culture, Tourism and InformationHeadquartersTegucigalpa, HondurasAnnual budgetHNL 216 m (2012)Minister responsibleTulio Mariano Gonzáles The Secretary of State for Culture, Arts and Sports (informally Culture Secretary) is a Honduras secretary of State responsible for the formula...
Harootiun Vehabedian, Patriark Armenia Yerusalem, 1900 (Library of Congress). Pada tahun 638, Gereja Apostolik Armenia mulai menunjuk uskupnya sendiri di Yerusalem, umumnya dikenal sebagai Patriark Armenia Yerusalem. Jabatan terus berlanjut, dengan beberapa interupsi, hingga hari ini. Uskup di Patriarkat Armenia Yerusalem diberi gelar Patriark untuk menghormati status suci Yerusalem dalam agama Kristen dan memiliki yurisdiksi independen dari Katolik Armenia dan Semua Orang Armenia. Gelar Patr...
Manga artist Makoto Raiku's signature in 2006 Makoto Kawada (河田 誠, Kawada Makoto, born 23 August 1974 in Gifu, Japan),[1] known by the pen name Makoto Raiku (雷句誠, Raiku Makoto), is a manga artist known for creating the Zatch Bell! franchise. Starting off an assistant for Kazuhiro Fujita on his manga Ushio & Tora, he began creating several one-shots for the Weekly Shōnen Sunday shōnen manga anthology such as Bird Man (about a young pilot), Hero Ba-Ban (about a cheerfu...
Chinese actor and singer Ren JialunBornRen Guochao (1989-04-11) 11 April 1989 (age 34)Qingdao, Shandong, ChinaOther namesAllen RenOccupationsActorSingerDancerModelYears active2014–presentAgent(s)H&R Century Pictures Co.,Ltd Ren Jialun (Chinese: 任嘉伦; born Ren Guochao on 11 April 1989), also known as Allen Ren, is a Chinese actor and singer. He is best known for his historical drama The Glory of Tang Dynasty (2017), Under The Power (2019), Forever and Ever, One an...
1955 film by Charles Lamont This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Carolina Cannonball – news · newspapers · books · scholar · JSTOR (February 2008) (Learn how and when to remove this template message) Carolina CannonballTheatrical release posterDirected byCharles LamontWritten byFrank GillBarry Shi...
Bagian dari seri tentangLiberalisme Mazhab Sejarah liberalisme Sumbangan bagi teori liberal Pemikiran Liberalisme konservatif Liberalisme budaya Kapitalisme demokratik Pendidikan demokratik Liberalisme ekonomi Egalitarianisme Perdagangan bebas Prinsip bahaya Individualisme Laissez-faire Demokrasi liberal Kenetralan liberal Ekonomi pasar Kebebasan negatif / positif Masyarakat terbuka Masyarakat permisif Kebebasan politik Kedaulatan rakyat Hak (individu) Sekularisme Pemisahan agama dan negara J...
Sulawesi UtaraNama lengkapTim sepak bola Provinsi Sulawesi UtaraStadionStadion Klabat(Kapasitas: 10.000)LigaPONPra PON 2024Peringkat 3 di Grup E Kostum kandang Tim sepak bola Provinsi Sulawesi Utara atau Tim sepak bola Sulawesi Utara adalah tim provinsial yang mewakili Sulawesi Utara dalam cabang olahraga sepak bola pada Pekan Olahraga Nasional. Tim ini dikendalikan oleh Asosiasi Provinsi Persatuan Sepak bola Seluruh Indonesia Sulawesi Utara (Asprov PSSI Sulut), yang merupakan anggota PSSI. P...
American actress (1864–1936) Alice DavenportDavenport in 1891BornAlice Shepphard(1864-02-29)February 29, 1864New York City, New York, USDiedJune 24, 1936(1936-06-24) (aged 72)Los Angeles, California, USOccupationActressYears active1911-1930Spouses Harry Davenport (m. 1893; div. 1896) Edwin H. Morse (died 1936) ChildrenDorothy Davenport Alice Davenport (née Shepphard; February 29, 1864 – June ...
This article is about the Polish newspaper. For the British newspaper, see Dziennik Polski (United Kingdom). Dziennik PolskiTypeDaily newspaperPublisherWydawnictwo Jagiellonia SAFounded1945LanguagePolishHeadquartersKraków, PolandCirculation21,133 (August 2014)ISSN0137-9089Websitedziennikpolski24.pl Dziennik Polski is a Polish newspaper. It was established in 1945 as a regional newspaper for Lesser Poland region. The circulation of the paper was 87,000 copies in 2003.[1] Its print and...
1930 film For the 1988 film, see Fair Game (1988 film). This article has multiple issues. Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page. (Learn how and when to remove these template messages) This article needs additional citations for verification. Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources. Unsourced material may be challenged and removed.Find sources: Mamba film – news · newspapers · books · scholar...
Douglas Sirk nel 1955 Douglas Sirk, nato Hans Detlef Sierck (Amburgo, 26 aprile 1897 – Lugano, 14 gennaio 1987), è stato un regista tedesco. Iniziò la sua carriera in Germania con il nome di Detlef Sierck ma lasciò il suo paese dopo la salita al potere dei nazionalsocialisti. Approdato negli Stati Uniti, diventò internazionalmente noto con il nome americanizzato di Douglas Sirk con il quale firmò alcuni fra i più bei film della Hollywood classica. A lungo considerato come regista di s...
Mexican professional wrestler Tigre UnoTigre Uno at Bound for Glory in October 2015Born (1981-04-04) April 4, 1981 (age 42)[1]Tijuana, Baja California, Mexico[2]Professional wrestling careerRing name(s)Extreme TigerTyger MaskTigre UnoUltimate TigerXtreme TigerBilled height5 ft 3 in (1.60 m)[3]Billed weight148 lb (67 kg)[3]Billed fromTijuana, MexicoTrained byRey Misterio, Sr.[1]DebutSeptember 13, 1998[1] Tigre Uno (b...
MS Rotterdam El Rotterdam en el año 2021.HistorialAstillero FincantieriTipo cruceroOperador Holland America LinePuerto de registro RóterdamAsignado 2021Destino En servicio activoEslora 296 metros[editar datos en Wikidata] El MS Rotterdam es un crucero de la clase Pinnacle, operado recientemente por Holland America Line (HAL), filial de Carnival Corporation & plc. Originalmente llamado Ryndam en desarrollo, pasó a llamarse Rotterdam en julio de 2020 durante la construcción pa...
В Википедии есть статьи о других людях с фамилией Ромер. Эдвард Ян Ромер Дата рождения 1806[1][2][…] или 14 мая 1806(1806-05-14) Место рождения Вильна, Российская империя Дата смерти 1878[1][2][…] или 15 мая 1878(1878-05-15) Место смерти Вильна, Российская империя Стр...
سكايلر جيسوندو (بالإنجليزية: Skyler Gisondo) معلومات شخصية اسم الولادة (بالإنجليزية: Skyler Augustus Gisondo) الميلاد 22 يوليو 1996 (العمر 27 سنة)فلوريدا، الولايات المتحدة مواطنة الولايات المتحدة الحياة العملية المهنة ممثل اللغة الأم الإنجليزية اللغات الإنجليزية سنوات الن...
Questa voce sull'argomento atleti spagnoli è solo un abbozzo. Contribuisci a migliorarla secondo le convenzioni di Wikipedia. Segui i suggerimenti del progetto di riferimento. Mercedes Chilla Nazionalità Spagna Altezza 169 cm Atletica leggera Specialità Lancio del giavellotto Palmarès Competizione Ori Argenti Bronzi Europei 0 0 1 Giochi del Mediterraneo 0 0 1 Universiadi 0 0 1 Europei under 23 0 1 0 Per maggiori dettagli vedi qui Modifica dati su Wikidata · Manual...
Den här artikeln har skapats av Lsjbot, ett program (en robot) för automatisk redigering. (2015-11)Artikeln kan innehålla fakta- eller språkfel, eller ett märkligt urval av fakta, källor eller bilder. Mallen kan avlägsnas efter en kontroll av innehållet (vidare information) Sankyaku Yama Kulle Kontinent Antarktis Höjdläge 100 m ö.h. Koordinater 68°35′00″S 41°02′00″Ö / 68.58333°S 41.03333°Ö / -68.58333; 41.03333 Geonames 6624747...
Strategi Solo vs Squad di Free Fire: Cara Menang Mudah!